maximally consistent (original) (raw)
Below are some basic properties of a maximally consistent set Δ:
- Δ is complete
: Δ⊢A or Δ⊢¬A for any wff A.
- Δ is complete
- for any wff A, either A∈Δ or ¬A∈Δ.
- If A∉Δ, then Δ∪{A} is not consistent.
- ⟂∉Δ.
- A→B∈Δ iff A∈Δ implies B∈Δ.
- A∧B∈Δ iff A∈Δ and B∈Δ.
- A∨B∈Δ iff A∈Δ or B∈Δ.
Proof.
- If A∈Δ, then clearly Δ⊢A. Conversely, suppose Δ⊢A. Let ℰ be a deduction
of A from Δ, and Γ:=Δ∪{A}. Suppose Γ⊢B. Let ℰ1 be a deduction of B from Γ, then ℰ,ℰ1 is a deduction of B from Δ, so Δ⊢B. Since Δ⊬⟂, Γ⊬⟂, so Γ is consistent. Since Δ is maximal, Γ=Δ, or A∈Δ.
- If A∈Δ, then clearly Δ⊢A. Conversely, suppose Δ⊢A. Let ℰ be a deduction
- Suppose Δ⊬A, then A∉Δ by 1. Then Δ∪{A} is not consistent (since Δ is maximal), which means Δ,A⊢⟂, or Δ⊢A→⟂, or Δ⊢¬A.
- If A∉Δ, then Δ⊬A by 1, so Δ⊢¬A by 2, and therefore ¬A∈Δ by 1 again.
- If A∉Δ, then ¬A∈Δ by 3., so that ¬A,A,⟂ is a deduction of ⟂ from Δ∪{A}, showing that Δ∪{A} is not consistent.
- If A is a theorem, then Δ⊢A, so that A∈Δ by 1. If A∈Δ and A→B∈Δ, then A,A→B,B is a deduction of B from Δ, so B∈Δ by 1.
- This is true for any consistent set.
- Suppose A→B∈Δ. If A∈Δ, then B∈Δ since Δ is closed under modus ponens. Conversely, suppose A∈Δ implies B∈Δ. This means that Δ,A⊢B. Then Δ⊢A→B by the deduction theorem
, and therefore A→B∈Δ by 1.
- Suppose A→B∈Δ. If A∈Δ, then B∈Δ since Δ is closed under modus ponens. Conversely, suppose A∈Δ implies B∈Δ. This means that Δ,A⊢B. Then Δ⊢A→B by the deduction theorem
- Suppose A∧B∈Δ, then by modus ponens on theorems A∧B→A and A∧B→B, we get A,B∈Δ, since Δ is a logic by 5. Conversely, suppose A,B∈Δ, then by modus ponens twice on theorem A→(B→A∧B), we get A∧B∈Δ by 5.
- Suppose A∨B∈Δ. Then ¬(¬A∧¬B)∈Δ by the definition of ∨, so ¬A∧¬B∉Δ by 3., which means ¬A∉Δ or ¬B∉Δ by the contrapositive of 8, or A∈Δ or B∈Δ by 3. Conversely, suppose A∈Δ or B∈Δ. Then by modus ponens on theorems A→A∨B or B→A∨B respectively, we get A∨B∈Δ by 5.
∎
The converses of 2 and 3 above are true too, and they provide alternative definitions of maximal consistency.
- any complete consistent theory is maximally consistent.
- any consistent set satisfying the condition in 3 above is maximally consistent.
Proof.
Suppose Δ is complete consistent. Let Γ be a consistent superset of Δ. Γ is also complete. If A∈Γ-Δ, then Γ⊢A, so Γ⊬¬A since Γ is consistent. But then Δ⊬¬A since Γ is a superset of Δ, which means Δ⊢A since Δ is complete. But then A∈Δ since Δ is deductively closed, which is a contradiction. Hence Δ is maximal.
Next, suppose Δ is consistent satisfying the condition: either A∈Δ or ¬A∈Δ for any wff A. Suppose Γ is a consistent superset of Δ. If A∈Γ-Δ, then ¬A∈Δ by assumption, which means ¬A∈Γ since Γ is a superset of Δ. But then both A and ¬A are deducible from Γ, contradicting the assumption that Γ is consistent. Therefore, Γ is not a proper superset of Δ, or Γ=Δ. ∎
Remarks.
- •
In the converse of 2, we require that Δ be a theory, for there are complete consistent sets that are not deductively closed. One such an example is the set V of all propositional variables: it can be shown that for every wff A, exactly one of V⊢A or V⊢¬A holds. - •
So far, none of the above actually tell us that a maximally consistent set exists. However, by Zorn’s lemma, it is not hard to see that such a set does exist. For more detail, see here (http://planetmath.org/LindenbaumsLemma). - •
There is also a semantic characterizationof a maximally consistent set: a set is maximally consistent iff there is a unique valuation
v such that v(A)=1 for every wff A in the set (see here (http://planetmath.org/CompactnessTheoremForClassicalPropositionalLogic)).