Umut Baysan | University of Oxford (original) (raw)

Papers by Umut Baysan

Research paper thumbnail of Rejecting Epiphobia (Synthese, forthcoming)

Synthese

Epiphenomenalism denies some or all putative cases of mental causation. The view is widely taken ... more Epiphenomenalism denies some or all putative cases of mental causation. The view is widely taken to be absurd: if a theory can be shown to entail epiphenomenalism, many see that as a reductio of that theory. Opponents take epiphenomenalism to be absurd because they regard the view as undermining the evident agency we have in action and precluding substantial self-knowledge. In this paper, I defend epiphenomenalism against these objections, and thus against the negative dialectical role that the view plays in philosophy of mind. I argue that nearly in all cases where a theory implies one kind of epiphenomenalism, it is an epiphenomenalism of a non-problematic kind, at least as far as issues about agency and self-knowledge are concerned. There is indeed a problematic version of epiphenomenalism, but that version is not relevant to the debates where its apparent absurdity is invoked.

Research paper thumbnail of Mad Qualia (Philosophical Quarterly, 2019)

This paper revisits some classic thought experiments in which experiences are detached from their... more This paper revisits some classic thought experiments in which experiences are detached from their characteristic causal roles, and it explores what these thought experiments tell us about qualia epiphenomenalism, i.e., the view that qualia are epiphenomenal properties. It argues that qualia epiphenomenalism is true just in case it is (nomologically) possible for experiences of the same type to have entirely different causal profiles. One conclusion is that even if qualia epiphenomenalism is false, it is not obvious that it is false. Connections between qualia epiphenomenalism, physicalism and nonphysicalist property dualism are further explored.

Research paper thumbnail of Epiphenomenal Properties (Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2018)

What is an epiphenomenal property? This question needs to be settled before we can decide whether... more What is an epiphenomenal property? This question needs to be settled before we can decide whether higher-level properties are epiphenomenal or not. In this paper, I offer an account of what it is for a property to have some causal power. From this, I derive a characterisation of the notion of an epiphenomenal property. I then argue that physically realized higher-level properties are not epiphenomenal because laws of nature impose causal similarities on the bearers of such properties, and these similarities figure as powers in the causal profiles of these properties.

Research paper thumbnail of Lawful Mimickers (Analysis, 2017)

The nomic view of dispositions holds that properties confer dispositions on their bearers with no... more The nomic view of dispositions holds that properties confer dispositions on their bearers with nomological necessity. The argument against nomic dispositions challenges the nomic view: if the nomic view is true, then objects don't have dispositions, but 'mimic' them. This paper presents an explication of disposition conferral which shows that the nomic view is not vulnerable to this objection.

Research paper thumbnail of Causal Emergence and Epiphenomenal Emergence (Erkenntnis, 2020)

According to one conception of strong emergence, strongly emergent properties are nomologically n... more According to one conception of strong emergence, strongly emergent properties are nomologically necessitated by their base properties and have novel causal powers relative to them. In this paper, I raise a difficulty for this conception of strong emergence, arguing that these two features (i.e., nomological necessitation and causal novelty) are incompatible. Instead of presenting this as an objection to the friends of strong emergence, I argue that this suggests that there are distinct varieties of strong emergence: causal emergence and epiphenomenal emergence. I then explore the prospects of emergentism with this distinction in the background.

Research paper thumbnail of Must Strong Emergence Collapse (Baysan, Umut & Wilson, Jessica, Philosophica,  2018)

Some claim that the notion of strong emergence as involving ontological or causal novelty makes n... more Some claim that the notion of strong emergence as involving ontological or causal novelty makes no sense, on grounds that any purportedly strongly emergent features or associated powers 'collapse', one way or another, into the lower-level base features upon which they depend. Here we argue that there are several independently motivated and defensible means of preventing the collapse of strongly emergent features or powers into their lower-level bases, as directed against a conception of strongly emergent features as having fundamentally novel powers. We first motivate and present the powers-based account (Section 1); we then canvass the two main versions of the collapse objection, show how these apply to the powers-based account, and problematize certain strategies of response (Section 2); we then present and defend four better strategies of response (Section 3).

Research paper thumbnail of Quidditism and Contingent Laws (Thought, 2019)

Thought: A Journal of Philosophy

According to contingentism, laws of nature hold contingently. An objection to contingentism is th... more According to contingentism, laws of nature hold contingently. An objection to contingentism is that it implies quidditism, and therefore inherits its implausible consequences. This paper argues that this objection is misguided. Understood one way, quidditism is not an implication of contingentism, hence even if it has implausible consequences, these are not relevant to contingentism. Understood another way, quidditism is implied by contingentism, but it is less clear if this version of quidditism has the same implausible consequences. Whatever the merits of contingentism, the argument from anti-quidditism is not successful in showing that it is false.

Research paper thumbnail of Why Incompatibilism about Mental Causation is Incompatible with Non-Reductive Physicalism (Inquiry, forthcoming)

Inquiry

The exclusion problem is meant to show that non-reductive physicalism leads to epiphenomenalism: ... more The exclusion problem is meant to show that non-reductive physicalism leads to epiphenomenalism: if mental properties are not identical with physical properties, then they are not causally efficacious. Defenders of a difference-making account of causation suggest that the exclusion problem can be solved because mental properties can be difference-making causes of physical effects. Here, we focus on what we dub an incompatibilist implementation of this general strategy and argue against it from a non-reductive physicalist perspective. Specifically, we argue that incompatibilism undermines either the non-reductionist or the physicalist aspirations of non-reductive physicalism.

Research paper thumbnail of An Argument for Power Inheritance (Philosophical Quarterly, 2016)

Non-reductive physicalism is commonly understood as the view that mental properties are realized ... more Non-reductive physicalism is commonly understood as the view that mental properties are realized by physical properties. Here, I argue that the realization relation in question is a power inheritance relation: if a property P realizes a property Q, then the causal powers of Q are a subset of the causal powers of P. Whereas others have motivated this claim by appealing to its theoretical benefits, I argue that it is in fact entailed by two theses: (i) realization is a same-subject necessitation relation; (ii) properties have their causal powers derivatively on the causal powers of their bearers. Although the power inheritance claim that is defended here has many opponents, I take it that the two theses that entail it are either plausible or widely assumed.

Research paper thumbnail of Realization Relations in Metaphysics (Minds and Machines, 2015)

“Realization” is a technical term that is used by metaphysicians, philosophers of mind, and philo... more “Realization” is a technical term that is used by metaphysicians, philosophers of mind, and philosophers of science to denote some dependence relation that is thought to obtain between higher-level properties and lower-level properties. It is said that mental properties are realized by physical properties; functional and computational properties are realized by first-order properties that occupy certain causal/functional roles; dispositional properties are realized by categorical properties; so on and so forth. Given this wide usage of the term “realization”, it would be right to think that there might be different dependence relations that this term denotes in different cases. Any relation that is aptly picked out by this term can be taken to be a realization relation. The aim of this state-of-the-field article is to introduce the central questions about the concept of realization, and provide formulations of a number of realization relations. In doing so, I identify some theoretical roles realization relations should play, and discuss some theories of realization in relation to these theoretical roles.

Research paper thumbnail of Realization (Oxford Bibliographies in Philosophy, 2015)

“Realization” is a technical term used by philosophers of mind, philosophers of science, and meta... more “Realization” is a technical term used by philosophers of mind, philosophers of science, and metaphysicians to denote some dependence relation that is thought to exist between higher-level properties or states and lower-level properties or states. Some philosophers of mind maintain that mental properties, such as believing that it is raining, having a painful sensation, and so on, are realized by physical properties. Understood this way, the term was introduced to philosophy of mind literature with the thesis that mental properties are multiply realizable by physical properties. Since different physical properties could realize the same mental property, it is thought that the phenomenon of multiple realization shows that the identity theory, namely the view that mental properties are identical with physical properties, is false. For similar reasons, some philosophers of the special sciences think that higher-level properties, such as biological properties, are realized by properties that are invoked in lower-level sciences such as physics. Some metaphysicians suggest that determinable properties, such as color properties (e.g., being red) are realized by their determinate properties (e.g., being crimson, being scarlet). Some philosophers maintain that dispositional properties, such as being fragile, are realized by nondispositional, categorical microstructural properties. It has been customary to think that functional properties, such as being a carburetor, are realized by first-order properties that play the specified functional roles. Due to the widely different usages of “realization,” it is difficult to determine if there should be one relation or several relations that this term denotes. Any relation that is denoted by this term can be seen as a realization relation. This article is about such relations. Whereas some theories explicitly formulate realization relations, some tangential theories that concern related issues (e.g., the mind-body problem) make crucial claims as to what counts as a case of realization. This article introduces the central questions about realization and clarifies the main issues and concepts that are invoked in the relevant literature.

Research paper thumbnail of Emergence, Function and Realization (Routledge Handbook of Emergence, 2019)

“Realization” and “emergence” are two concepts that are sometimes used to describe same or simila... more “Realization” and “emergence” are two concepts that are sometimes used to describe same or similar phenomena in philosophy of mind and the special sciences, where such phenomena involve the synchronic dependence of some higher-level states of affairs on the lower-level ones. According to a popular line of thought, higher-level properties that are invoked in the special sciences are realized by, and/or emergent from, lower-level, broadly physical, properties. So, these two concepts are taken to refer to relations between properties from different levels where the lower-level ones somehow “bring about” the higher-level ones. However, for those who specialise in inter-level relations, there are important differences between these two concepts – especially if emergence is understood as strong emergence. The purpose of this chapter is to highlight these differences.

Research paper thumbnail of Causal Powers and the Necessity of Realization (IJPS, 2017)

Non-reductive physicalists hold that mental properties are realized by physical properties. The r... more Non-reductive physicalists hold that mental properties are realized by physical properties. The realization relation is typically taken to be a metaphysical necessitation relation. Here, I explore how the metaphysical necessitation feature of realization can be explained by what is known as " the subset view " of realization. The subset view holds that the causal powers that are associated with a realized property are a proper subset of the causal powers that are associated with the realizer property. I argue that the said explanation of the metaphysical necessitation feature requires a careful treatment of the relationship between properties and causal powers.
(DOI: 10.1080/09672559.2017.1332081)

Research paper thumbnail of Memory, Confabulation, and Epistemic Failure (Logos & Episteme, forthcoming)

Research paper thumbnail of Sensory Substitution and Non-Sensory Feelings

Sensory Substitution and Augmentation, Fiona Macpherson (Ed.), Oxford University Press, 2019

One of the central limitations of sensory substitution devices (SSDs) is their inability to repro... more One of the central limitations of sensory substitution devices (SSDs) is their inability to reproduce the non-sensory feelings that are normally associated with visual experiences, especially hedonic and aesthetic responses. This limitation is sometimes reported to cause SSD users frustration. To make matters worse, it is unclear that improvements in acuity, bandwidth, or training will resolve the issue. Yet, if SSDs are to actually reproduce visual experience in its fullness, it seems that the reproduction of non-sensory feelings will be of some importance. We offer a novel solution. Researchers can produce hedonic and aesthetic responses by eliciting these feelings artificially, pairing distal objects that should be pleasurable to pleasurable stimulus outputs from the SSD. We outline two strategies for accomplishing this: first, by means of a prefixed, hardwired, association of pleasant distal objects to pleasant stimulus outputs from the SSD; second, by means of a flexible, feedback-based association which creates associations based on a subject-directed matching of distal objects to patterns of stimuli from the SSD which the subject takes to have the corresponding hedonic properties. We evaluate some problems with both strategies, and we argue that the feedback-based strategy is more promising. Researchers can use this strategy to help the blind, allowing them to take pleasure in the objects they perceive using SSDs.

Research paper thumbnail of A New Response to the New Evil Demon Problem (Logos & Episteme, 2017)

The New Evil Demon Problem is meant to show that reliabilism about epistemic justification is inc... more The New Evil Demon Problem is meant to show that reliabilism about epistemic justification is incompatible with the intuitive idea that the external-world beliefs of a subject who is the victim of a Cartesian demon could be epistemically justified. Here, I present a new argument that such beliefs can be justified on reliabilism. Whereas others have argued for this conclusion by making some alterations in the formulation of reliabilism, I argue that, as far as the said problem is concerned, such alterations are redundant. No reliabilist should fear the demon.

Book Reviews by Umut Baysan

Research paper thumbnail of Review of Mental Causation: A Counterfactual Theory (NDPR, 2020)

Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, 2020

Research paper thumbnail of Review of the Multiple Realization Book (Analysis, 2017)

Research paper thumbnail of Review of Qualia and Mental Causation in a Physical World: Themes from the Philosophy of Jaegwon Kim (Philosophical Quarterly, 2016)

Jaegwon Kim's contributions to philosophy of mind have focused on trying to find a place for ment... more Jaegwon Kim's contributions to philosophy of mind have focused on trying to find a place for mental phenomena in the causal order of events in the physical world. For decades, he has argued that mental properties can't be causally efficacious unless they are somehow reducible to physical properties—given the hypothesis that the physical world is causally closed. On this point, he has been an opponent of non-reductive physicalism (NRP), which accepts the broadly physicalist worldview but denies psycho-physical identities; according to NRP, mental properties are not identical with, but are realized by, physical properties. Kim's latest position is that some form of reduction may be possible for intentional mental properties (such as desires, beliefs, and so on) because they are ‘functionalizable’. Yet, he thinks that qualia aren't reducible to physical properties, because they are not functionalizable. In fact, for the last decade or so, Kim has accepted the limitations of physicalism with respect to qualia, and offered a form of property dualism about mental properties. Qualia and Mental Causation in a Physical World is an edited volume with contributions from some of the most distinguished philosophers in the literature who respond to Kim on pretty much every point mentioned in this paragraph.

Research paper thumbnail of Review of Mental Causation and Ontology (Mind, 2014)

Research paper thumbnail of Rejecting Epiphobia (Synthese, forthcoming)

Synthese

Epiphenomenalism denies some or all putative cases of mental causation. The view is widely taken ... more Epiphenomenalism denies some or all putative cases of mental causation. The view is widely taken to be absurd: if a theory can be shown to entail epiphenomenalism, many see that as a reductio of that theory. Opponents take epiphenomenalism to be absurd because they regard the view as undermining the evident agency we have in action and precluding substantial self-knowledge. In this paper, I defend epiphenomenalism against these objections, and thus against the negative dialectical role that the view plays in philosophy of mind. I argue that nearly in all cases where a theory implies one kind of epiphenomenalism, it is an epiphenomenalism of a non-problematic kind, at least as far as issues about agency and self-knowledge are concerned. There is indeed a problematic version of epiphenomenalism, but that version is not relevant to the debates where its apparent absurdity is invoked.

Research paper thumbnail of Mad Qualia (Philosophical Quarterly, 2019)

This paper revisits some classic thought experiments in which experiences are detached from their... more This paper revisits some classic thought experiments in which experiences are detached from their characteristic causal roles, and it explores what these thought experiments tell us about qualia epiphenomenalism, i.e., the view that qualia are epiphenomenal properties. It argues that qualia epiphenomenalism is true just in case it is (nomologically) possible for experiences of the same type to have entirely different causal profiles. One conclusion is that even if qualia epiphenomenalism is false, it is not obvious that it is false. Connections between qualia epiphenomenalism, physicalism and nonphysicalist property dualism are further explored.

Research paper thumbnail of Epiphenomenal Properties (Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2018)

What is an epiphenomenal property? This question needs to be settled before we can decide whether... more What is an epiphenomenal property? This question needs to be settled before we can decide whether higher-level properties are epiphenomenal or not. In this paper, I offer an account of what it is for a property to have some causal power. From this, I derive a characterisation of the notion of an epiphenomenal property. I then argue that physically realized higher-level properties are not epiphenomenal because laws of nature impose causal similarities on the bearers of such properties, and these similarities figure as powers in the causal profiles of these properties.

Research paper thumbnail of Lawful Mimickers (Analysis, 2017)

The nomic view of dispositions holds that properties confer dispositions on their bearers with no... more The nomic view of dispositions holds that properties confer dispositions on their bearers with nomological necessity. The argument against nomic dispositions challenges the nomic view: if the nomic view is true, then objects don't have dispositions, but 'mimic' them. This paper presents an explication of disposition conferral which shows that the nomic view is not vulnerable to this objection.

Research paper thumbnail of Causal Emergence and Epiphenomenal Emergence (Erkenntnis, 2020)

According to one conception of strong emergence, strongly emergent properties are nomologically n... more According to one conception of strong emergence, strongly emergent properties are nomologically necessitated by their base properties and have novel causal powers relative to them. In this paper, I raise a difficulty for this conception of strong emergence, arguing that these two features (i.e., nomological necessitation and causal novelty) are incompatible. Instead of presenting this as an objection to the friends of strong emergence, I argue that this suggests that there are distinct varieties of strong emergence: causal emergence and epiphenomenal emergence. I then explore the prospects of emergentism with this distinction in the background.

Research paper thumbnail of Must Strong Emergence Collapse (Baysan, Umut & Wilson, Jessica, Philosophica,  2018)

Some claim that the notion of strong emergence as involving ontological or causal novelty makes n... more Some claim that the notion of strong emergence as involving ontological or causal novelty makes no sense, on grounds that any purportedly strongly emergent features or associated powers 'collapse', one way or another, into the lower-level base features upon which they depend. Here we argue that there are several independently motivated and defensible means of preventing the collapse of strongly emergent features or powers into their lower-level bases, as directed against a conception of strongly emergent features as having fundamentally novel powers. We first motivate and present the powers-based account (Section 1); we then canvass the two main versions of the collapse objection, show how these apply to the powers-based account, and problematize certain strategies of response (Section 2); we then present and defend four better strategies of response (Section 3).

Research paper thumbnail of Quidditism and Contingent Laws (Thought, 2019)

Thought: A Journal of Philosophy

According to contingentism, laws of nature hold contingently. An objection to contingentism is th... more According to contingentism, laws of nature hold contingently. An objection to contingentism is that it implies quidditism, and therefore inherits its implausible consequences. This paper argues that this objection is misguided. Understood one way, quidditism is not an implication of contingentism, hence even if it has implausible consequences, these are not relevant to contingentism. Understood another way, quidditism is implied by contingentism, but it is less clear if this version of quidditism has the same implausible consequences. Whatever the merits of contingentism, the argument from anti-quidditism is not successful in showing that it is false.

Research paper thumbnail of Why Incompatibilism about Mental Causation is Incompatible with Non-Reductive Physicalism (Inquiry, forthcoming)

Inquiry

The exclusion problem is meant to show that non-reductive physicalism leads to epiphenomenalism: ... more The exclusion problem is meant to show that non-reductive physicalism leads to epiphenomenalism: if mental properties are not identical with physical properties, then they are not causally efficacious. Defenders of a difference-making account of causation suggest that the exclusion problem can be solved because mental properties can be difference-making causes of physical effects. Here, we focus on what we dub an incompatibilist implementation of this general strategy and argue against it from a non-reductive physicalist perspective. Specifically, we argue that incompatibilism undermines either the non-reductionist or the physicalist aspirations of non-reductive physicalism.

Research paper thumbnail of An Argument for Power Inheritance (Philosophical Quarterly, 2016)

Non-reductive physicalism is commonly understood as the view that mental properties are realized ... more Non-reductive physicalism is commonly understood as the view that mental properties are realized by physical properties. Here, I argue that the realization relation in question is a power inheritance relation: if a property P realizes a property Q, then the causal powers of Q are a subset of the causal powers of P. Whereas others have motivated this claim by appealing to its theoretical benefits, I argue that it is in fact entailed by two theses: (i) realization is a same-subject necessitation relation; (ii) properties have their causal powers derivatively on the causal powers of their bearers. Although the power inheritance claim that is defended here has many opponents, I take it that the two theses that entail it are either plausible or widely assumed.

Research paper thumbnail of Realization Relations in Metaphysics (Minds and Machines, 2015)

“Realization” is a technical term that is used by metaphysicians, philosophers of mind, and philo... more “Realization” is a technical term that is used by metaphysicians, philosophers of mind, and philosophers of science to denote some dependence relation that is thought to obtain between higher-level properties and lower-level properties. It is said that mental properties are realized by physical properties; functional and computational properties are realized by first-order properties that occupy certain causal/functional roles; dispositional properties are realized by categorical properties; so on and so forth. Given this wide usage of the term “realization”, it would be right to think that there might be different dependence relations that this term denotes in different cases. Any relation that is aptly picked out by this term can be taken to be a realization relation. The aim of this state-of-the-field article is to introduce the central questions about the concept of realization, and provide formulations of a number of realization relations. In doing so, I identify some theoretical roles realization relations should play, and discuss some theories of realization in relation to these theoretical roles.

Research paper thumbnail of Realization (Oxford Bibliographies in Philosophy, 2015)

“Realization” is a technical term used by philosophers of mind, philosophers of science, and meta... more “Realization” is a technical term used by philosophers of mind, philosophers of science, and metaphysicians to denote some dependence relation that is thought to exist between higher-level properties or states and lower-level properties or states. Some philosophers of mind maintain that mental properties, such as believing that it is raining, having a painful sensation, and so on, are realized by physical properties. Understood this way, the term was introduced to philosophy of mind literature with the thesis that mental properties are multiply realizable by physical properties. Since different physical properties could realize the same mental property, it is thought that the phenomenon of multiple realization shows that the identity theory, namely the view that mental properties are identical with physical properties, is false. For similar reasons, some philosophers of the special sciences think that higher-level properties, such as biological properties, are realized by properties that are invoked in lower-level sciences such as physics. Some metaphysicians suggest that determinable properties, such as color properties (e.g., being red) are realized by their determinate properties (e.g., being crimson, being scarlet). Some philosophers maintain that dispositional properties, such as being fragile, are realized by nondispositional, categorical microstructural properties. It has been customary to think that functional properties, such as being a carburetor, are realized by first-order properties that play the specified functional roles. Due to the widely different usages of “realization,” it is difficult to determine if there should be one relation or several relations that this term denotes. Any relation that is denoted by this term can be seen as a realization relation. This article is about such relations. Whereas some theories explicitly formulate realization relations, some tangential theories that concern related issues (e.g., the mind-body problem) make crucial claims as to what counts as a case of realization. This article introduces the central questions about realization and clarifies the main issues and concepts that are invoked in the relevant literature.

Research paper thumbnail of Emergence, Function and Realization (Routledge Handbook of Emergence, 2019)

“Realization” and “emergence” are two concepts that are sometimes used to describe same or simila... more “Realization” and “emergence” are two concepts that are sometimes used to describe same or similar phenomena in philosophy of mind and the special sciences, where such phenomena involve the synchronic dependence of some higher-level states of affairs on the lower-level ones. According to a popular line of thought, higher-level properties that are invoked in the special sciences are realized by, and/or emergent from, lower-level, broadly physical, properties. So, these two concepts are taken to refer to relations between properties from different levels where the lower-level ones somehow “bring about” the higher-level ones. However, for those who specialise in inter-level relations, there are important differences between these two concepts – especially if emergence is understood as strong emergence. The purpose of this chapter is to highlight these differences.

Research paper thumbnail of Causal Powers and the Necessity of Realization (IJPS, 2017)

Non-reductive physicalists hold that mental properties are realized by physical properties. The r... more Non-reductive physicalists hold that mental properties are realized by physical properties. The realization relation is typically taken to be a metaphysical necessitation relation. Here, I explore how the metaphysical necessitation feature of realization can be explained by what is known as " the subset view " of realization. The subset view holds that the causal powers that are associated with a realized property are a proper subset of the causal powers that are associated with the realizer property. I argue that the said explanation of the metaphysical necessitation feature requires a careful treatment of the relationship between properties and causal powers.
(DOI: 10.1080/09672559.2017.1332081)

Research paper thumbnail of Memory, Confabulation, and Epistemic Failure (Logos & Episteme, forthcoming)

Research paper thumbnail of Sensory Substitution and Non-Sensory Feelings

Sensory Substitution and Augmentation, Fiona Macpherson (Ed.), Oxford University Press, 2019

One of the central limitations of sensory substitution devices (SSDs) is their inability to repro... more One of the central limitations of sensory substitution devices (SSDs) is their inability to reproduce the non-sensory feelings that are normally associated with visual experiences, especially hedonic and aesthetic responses. This limitation is sometimes reported to cause SSD users frustration. To make matters worse, it is unclear that improvements in acuity, bandwidth, or training will resolve the issue. Yet, if SSDs are to actually reproduce visual experience in its fullness, it seems that the reproduction of non-sensory feelings will be of some importance. We offer a novel solution. Researchers can produce hedonic and aesthetic responses by eliciting these feelings artificially, pairing distal objects that should be pleasurable to pleasurable stimulus outputs from the SSD. We outline two strategies for accomplishing this: first, by means of a prefixed, hardwired, association of pleasant distal objects to pleasant stimulus outputs from the SSD; second, by means of a flexible, feedback-based association which creates associations based on a subject-directed matching of distal objects to patterns of stimuli from the SSD which the subject takes to have the corresponding hedonic properties. We evaluate some problems with both strategies, and we argue that the feedback-based strategy is more promising. Researchers can use this strategy to help the blind, allowing them to take pleasure in the objects they perceive using SSDs.

Research paper thumbnail of A New Response to the New Evil Demon Problem (Logos & Episteme, 2017)

The New Evil Demon Problem is meant to show that reliabilism about epistemic justification is inc... more The New Evil Demon Problem is meant to show that reliabilism about epistemic justification is incompatible with the intuitive idea that the external-world beliefs of a subject who is the victim of a Cartesian demon could be epistemically justified. Here, I present a new argument that such beliefs can be justified on reliabilism. Whereas others have argued for this conclusion by making some alterations in the formulation of reliabilism, I argue that, as far as the said problem is concerned, such alterations are redundant. No reliabilist should fear the demon.

Research paper thumbnail of Review of Mental Causation: A Counterfactual Theory (NDPR, 2020)

Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, 2020

Research paper thumbnail of Review of the Multiple Realization Book (Analysis, 2017)

Research paper thumbnail of Review of Qualia and Mental Causation in a Physical World: Themes from the Philosophy of Jaegwon Kim (Philosophical Quarterly, 2016)

Jaegwon Kim's contributions to philosophy of mind have focused on trying to find a place for ment... more Jaegwon Kim's contributions to philosophy of mind have focused on trying to find a place for mental phenomena in the causal order of events in the physical world. For decades, he has argued that mental properties can't be causally efficacious unless they are somehow reducible to physical properties—given the hypothesis that the physical world is causally closed. On this point, he has been an opponent of non-reductive physicalism (NRP), which accepts the broadly physicalist worldview but denies psycho-physical identities; according to NRP, mental properties are not identical with, but are realized by, physical properties. Kim's latest position is that some form of reduction may be possible for intentional mental properties (such as desires, beliefs, and so on) because they are ‘functionalizable’. Yet, he thinks that qualia aren't reducible to physical properties, because they are not functionalizable. In fact, for the last decade or so, Kim has accepted the limitations of physicalism with respect to qualia, and offered a form of property dualism about mental properties. Qualia and Mental Causation in a Physical World is an edited volume with contributions from some of the most distinguished philosophers in the literature who respond to Kim on pretty much every point mentioned in this paragraph.

Research paper thumbnail of Review of Mental Causation and Ontology (Mind, 2014)

Research paper thumbnail of The Mental Causation Question and Emergence (Published in iCog Blog)

This is a blog post on mental causation and emergence written for non-specialist readers.

Research paper thumbnail of Sensory Substitution and Augmentation Workshop Report