Thomas Feeney | University of St. Thomas, Minnesota (original) (raw)

Papers by Thomas Feeney

Research paper thumbnail of Leibniz's Early Theodicy and its Unwelcome Implications

The Leibniz Review, 2020

To explain why God is not the author of sin, despite grounding all features of the world, the ear... more To explain why God is not the author of sin, despite grounding all features of the world, the early Leibniz marginalized the divine will and defined existence as harmony. These moves support each other. It is easier to nearly eliminate the divine will from creation if existence itself is something wholly intelligible, and easier to identify existence with an internal feature of the possibles if the divine will is not responsible for creation. Both moves, however, commit Leibniz to a necessitarianism that is stronger than what prominent interpreters such as Robert Sleigh and Mogens Lærke have found in the early Leibniz, and stronger than the necessitarianism that threatens his later philosophy. I defend this reading of Leibniz and propose that some features of Leibniz’s later metaphysics, including his “striving possibles” doctrine, are an artifact of the effort to rescue the early theodicy from its unwelcome implications.

Research paper thumbnail of Cartesian Circles and the Analytic Method

International Philosophical Quarterly, 2020

The apparently circular arguments in Descartes's Meditations should be read as analytic arguments... more The apparently circular arguments in Descartes's Meditations should be read as analytic arguments, as Descartes himself suggested. This both explains and excuses the appearance of circularity. Analysis "digs out" what is already present in the meditator's mind but not yet "expressly known" (Letter to Voetius). Once this is achieved, the meditator may take the result of analysis as an epistemic starting point independent of the original argument. That is, analytic arguments may be reversed to yield demonstrative proofs that follow an already worked-out order of ideas. The "Cartesian Circle," for example, is circular only when Descartes's original analytic argument is mistaken for the demonstration it enables. This approach to Cartesian Circles is unlike the standard approach, which attempts to show that Descartes's original arguments do work as demonstrations after all.

Research paper thumbnail of Leibniz, Acosmism, and Incompossibility

Leibniz: Compossibility and Possible Worlds. Edited by Gregory Brown and Yual Chiek. Springer, 2016

Leibniz claims that God acts in the best possible way, and that this includes creating exactly on... more Leibniz claims that God acts in the best possible way, and that this includes creating exactly one world. But worlds are aggregates, and aggregates have a low degree of reality or metaphysical perfection, perhaps none at all. This is Leibniz’s tendency toward acosmism, or the view that there this no such thing as creation-as-a-whole. Many interpreters reconcile Leibniz’s acosmist tendency with the high value of worlds by proposing that God sums the value of each substance created, so that the best world is just the world with the most substances. I call this way of determining the value of a world the Additive Theory of Value (ATV), and argue that it leads to the current and insoluble form of the problem of incompossibility. To avoid the problem, I read “possible worlds” in “God chooses the best of all possible worlds” as referring to God’s ideas of worlds. These ideas, though built up from essences, are themselves unities and so well suited to be the value bearers that Leibniz’s theodicy requires. They have their own value, thanks to their unity, and that unity is not preserved when more essences are added.

Book Reviews by Thomas Feeney

Research paper thumbnail of Review of Lloyd Strickland's "Leibniz on God and Religion: A Reader"

American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 2019

Research paper thumbnail of Leibniz's Early Theodicy and its Unwelcome Implications

The Leibniz Review, 2020

To explain why God is not the author of sin, despite grounding all features of the world, the ear... more To explain why God is not the author of sin, despite grounding all features of the world, the early Leibniz marginalized the divine will and defined existence as harmony. These moves support each other. It is easier to nearly eliminate the divine will from creation if existence itself is something wholly intelligible, and easier to identify existence with an internal feature of the possibles if the divine will is not responsible for creation. Both moves, however, commit Leibniz to a necessitarianism that is stronger than what prominent interpreters such as Robert Sleigh and Mogens Lærke have found in the early Leibniz, and stronger than the necessitarianism that threatens his later philosophy. I defend this reading of Leibniz and propose that some features of Leibniz’s later metaphysics, including his “striving possibles” doctrine, are an artifact of the effort to rescue the early theodicy from its unwelcome implications.

Research paper thumbnail of Cartesian Circles and the Analytic Method

International Philosophical Quarterly, 2020

The apparently circular arguments in Descartes's Meditations should be read as analytic arguments... more The apparently circular arguments in Descartes's Meditations should be read as analytic arguments, as Descartes himself suggested. This both explains and excuses the appearance of circularity. Analysis "digs out" what is already present in the meditator's mind but not yet "expressly known" (Letter to Voetius). Once this is achieved, the meditator may take the result of analysis as an epistemic starting point independent of the original argument. That is, analytic arguments may be reversed to yield demonstrative proofs that follow an already worked-out order of ideas. The "Cartesian Circle," for example, is circular only when Descartes's original analytic argument is mistaken for the demonstration it enables. This approach to Cartesian Circles is unlike the standard approach, which attempts to show that Descartes's original arguments do work as demonstrations after all.

Research paper thumbnail of Leibniz, Acosmism, and Incompossibility

Leibniz: Compossibility and Possible Worlds. Edited by Gregory Brown and Yual Chiek. Springer, 2016

Leibniz claims that God acts in the best possible way, and that this includes creating exactly on... more Leibniz claims that God acts in the best possible way, and that this includes creating exactly one world. But worlds are aggregates, and aggregates have a low degree of reality or metaphysical perfection, perhaps none at all. This is Leibniz’s tendency toward acosmism, or the view that there this no such thing as creation-as-a-whole. Many interpreters reconcile Leibniz’s acosmist tendency with the high value of worlds by proposing that God sums the value of each substance created, so that the best world is just the world with the most substances. I call this way of determining the value of a world the Additive Theory of Value (ATV), and argue that it leads to the current and insoluble form of the problem of incompossibility. To avoid the problem, I read “possible worlds” in “God chooses the best of all possible worlds” as referring to God’s ideas of worlds. These ideas, though built up from essences, are themselves unities and so well suited to be the value bearers that Leibniz’s theodicy requires. They have their own value, thanks to their unity, and that unity is not preserved when more essences are added.

Research paper thumbnail of Review of Lloyd Strickland's "Leibniz on God and Religion: A Reader"

American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, 2019