Sonja Smets | University of Amsterdam (original) (raw)
Qualitative Logics for Belief Dynamics by Sonja Smets
We present a logical setting that incorporates a belief-revision mechanism within Dynamic-Epistem... more We present a logical setting that incorporates a belief-revision mechanism within Dynamic-Epistemic logic. As the " static " basis for belief revision, we use epistemic plausibility models, together with a modal language based on two epistemic operators: a " knowledge " modality K (the standard S5, fully introspective, notion), and a " safe belief " modality 2 (" weak " , non-negatively-introspective, notion, capturing a version of Lehrer's " indefeasible knowledge "). To deal with " dynamic " belief revision, we introduce action plausibility models, representing various types of " doxastic events ". Action models " act " on state models via a modified update product operation: the " Action-Priority " Update. This is the natural dynamic generalization of AGM revision, giving priority to the incoming information (i.e., to " actions ") over prior beliefs. We completely axiomatize this logic, and show how our update mechanism can " simulate " , in a uniform manner , many different belief-revision policies.
This chapter gives an overview of current dynamic logics that describe belief update and revision... more This chapter gives an overview of current dynamic logics that describe belief update and revision, both for single agents and in multi-agent settings. We employ a mixture of ideas from AGM belief revision theory and dynamic-epistemic logics of information-driven agency. After describing the basic background, we review logics of various kinds of beliefs based on plausibility models, and then go on to various sorts of belief change engendered by changes in current models through hard and soft information. We present matching complete logics with dynamic-epistemic recursion axioms, and develop a very general perspective on belief change by the use of event models and priority update. The chapter continues with three topics that naturally complement the setting of single steps of belief change: connections with probabilistic approaches to belief change, long-term temporal process structure including links with formal learning theory, and multi-agent scenarios of information flow and belief revision in games and social networks. We end with a discussion of alternative approaches, further directions, and windows to the broader literature, while links with relevant philosophical traditions are discussed throughout.
The pre-eminence of logical dynamics, over a static and purely propo-sitional view of Logic, lies... more The pre-eminence of logical dynamics, over a static and purely propo-sitional view of Logic, lies at the core of a new understanding of both formal epistemology and the logical foundations of quantum mechanics. Both areas appear at first sight to be based on purely static propositional formalisms, but in our view their fundamental operators are essentially dynamic in nature. Quantum logic can be best understood as the logic of physically-constrained informational interactions (in the form of measurements and entanglement) between subsystems of a global physical system. Similarly, (multi-agent) epistemic logic is the logic of socially-constrained informational interactions (in the form of direct observations, learning, various forms of communication and testimony) between " subsystems " of a social system. Dynamic Epistemic Logic (DEL) provides us with a unifying setting in which these informational interactions, coming from seemingly very different areas of research, can be fully compared and analyzed. The DEL formalism comes with a powerful set of tools that allows us to make the underlying dynamic/interactive mechanisms fully transparent.
Table of Contents, Preface written by J. van Benthem and Introduction written by A. Baltag and S.... more Table of Contents, Preface written by J. van Benthem and Introduction written by A. Baltag and S. Smets. BOOK: `Johan van Benthem on Logic and Information Dynamics' , Outstanding Contributions to Logic Series, Volume 4, 55 pages, pp. xv-lxix, Springer, 2014.
We present a complete, decidable logic for reasoning about a notion of completely trustworthy (" ... more We present a complete, decidable logic for reasoning about a notion of completely trustworthy (" conclusive ") evidence and its relations to justifiable (implicit) belief and knowledge, as well as to their explicit justifications. This logic makes use of a number of evidence-related notions such as availability, admissibility, and " goodness " of a piece of evidence, and is based on an innovative modification of the Fitting semantics for Artemov's Justification Logic designed to preempt Gettier-type counterexamples. We combine this with ideas from belief revision and awareness logics to provide an account for explicitly justified (defeasible) knowledge based on conclusive evidence that addresses the problem of (logical) omniscience.
We present a logic for reasoning about the evidence-based knowledge and beliefs and the evidentia... more We present a logic for reasoning about the evidence-based knowledge and beliefs and the evidential dynamics of non-logically-omniscient agents. We do this by adapting key tools and techniques from Dynamic Epistemic Logic, Justification Logic, and Belief Revision so as to provide a lightweight, yet fine-grained approach that characterizes well-known epistemic and doxastic attitudes in terms of the evidential reasoning that justifies these attitudes. We then add the dynamic operations of evidence introduction, evidence-based inference, strong acceptance of new evidence (evidential " upgrade "), and irrevocable acceptance of additional evidence (evidential " update "). We exemplify our theory by providing a formal dynamic account of Lehrer's well-known Gettier-type scenario involving the famous Ferrari and the infamous Messrs. Nogot and Havit.
In this paper we re-evaluate Segerberg's " full DDL " (Dynamic Doxas-tic Logic) from the perspect... more In this paper we re-evaluate Segerberg's " full DDL " (Dynamic Doxas-tic Logic) from the perspective of Dynamic Epistemic Logic (DEL), in its belief-revision-friendly incarnation. We argue that a correct version of full DDL must give up the Success Postulate for dynamic revision. Next, we present (an appropriately generalized and simplified version of) full DDL, showing that it is a generalization of the so-called Topo-logic of Moss and Parikh. We construct AGM-friendly versions of full DDL, corresponding to various revising/contracting operations considered in the Belief Revision literature. We show that DDL can internalize inside one model the " external " doxastic dynamics of DEL, as well as the evidential dynamics investigated by van Benthem and Pacuit. In our Conclusions section, we compare three styles of modeling doxastic dynamics: DDL, DEL and PDL/ETL (the Propo-sitional Dynamic Logic approach, with its Epistemic Temporal Logic variant).
We investigate the issue of reaching doxastic agreement among the agents of a group by " sharing ... more We investigate the issue of reaching doxastic agreement among the agents of a group by " sharing " information via successive acts of sincere, persuasive and public communication within the group. The topic relates to " preference aggregation " in Social Choice theory, where the problem is to find a natural and fair merge operation for aggregating the agents' preferences into a single group preference. In this paper we study this topic within the setting of Dynamic Epistemic Logic (DEL) and its recent extensions to belief revision theory. First we interpret the agents' preference relations as " doxastic preferences " or " doxastic plausibility orders ". Using these plausibility structures, we can express several types of relevant doxastic attitudes: ranging from an agent's simple beliefs and conditional beliefs to her defeasible knowledge and irrevocable knowledge. Next, we model communication via a series of doxastic/epistemic actions that affect the agent's plausibility structures. Because these structures can change in different ways, a group of agents has to adopt a specific communication protocol in order to aggregate their doxastic attitudes. We study the type of merges that are realizable via specific communication protocols and we highlight important factors which may influence the result, such as " the order of the speakers " , or the listeners' doxastic attitudes towards the speakers (i.e their opinions concerning the reliability of the incoming information).
While propositional doxastic attitudes , like knowledge and belief, capture an agent's opinion ab... more While propositional doxastic attitudes , like knowledge and belief, capture an agent's opinion about certain propositions, her attitudes towards sources of information express her opinion about the reliability (or trustwor-thiness) of those sources. If an agent trusts a witness, then she will, within certain limits, tend to accept his testimony as veridical. But if she considers the witness to be a notorious liar, she may come to believe the opposite of what he tells her. In this paper, we put such attitudes towards sources (or dynamic (doxastic) attitudes) center stage, and formalize them as belief-revision strategies: policies governing how an agent changess her beliefs whenever new information from a certain (type of) source is received. We present a semantic, qualitative modelling of this notion and investigate its properties .
We investigate the process of truth-seeking by iterated belief revision with higher-level doxasti... more We investigate the process of truth-seeking by iterated belief revision with higher-level doxastic information. In this paper we elaborate further on the main results and formal settings provided in [8, 7], linking this previous work to the issue of truth approximation. On the one hand our previous results show that on an initial finite Kripke model, a truthful belief upgrade (with the same true sentence) may be repeated 'ad infinitum', without ever reaching a fixed point of the belief-revision process. On the other hand, we proved some positive convergence results: the agent's simple beliefs (and knowledge) will eventually stabilize when iterating updates or truthful radical upgrades. In this paper we apply these results to the problem of convergence to the truth. We study the conditions under which the fixed points of iterated upgrades (if they are reached) would coincide with the truth. We highlight the case in which from some moment onwards, at least if the agent completely or highly trusts the source of new information, she can predict all the future correct answers to a series of questions (but without ever knowing for sure that this is the case). We give two different conditions ensuring that beliefs eventually converge on " full (complete) truth " , as well as conditions ensuring only that they converge to true (but not necessarily complete) beliefs.
What happens in the long term with a group’s beliefs, knowledge and “epistemic states” (fully des... more What happens in the long term with a group’s beliefs, knowledge and “epistemic states” (fully describable in fact by conditional beliefs), when receiving (or exchanging) a sequence of public announcements of truthful but uncertain information? Do the agents’ beliefs (or knowledge, or conditional beliefs, or other doxastic attitudes such as “strong beliefs”) reach a fixed point? Or do they exhibit instead a cyclic behavior, oscillating forever? These questions are of obvious importance for Belief Revision theory, Learning theory and Social Choice theory,
and may have some relevance to Game Theory as well. In fact, some of these questions came to our attention due to a recent talk by J. van Benthem (Chennai, January 2009), in which he was refining his previous “dynamic” analysis [14] of backward induction solution in perfect information games. This extended abstract provides some partial answers to some of the questions above, as well as a convenient setting for investigating further the ones that are still open.
We present a semantic analysis of the Ramsey test, pointing out its deep underlying flaw: the ten... more We present a semantic analysis of the Ramsey test, pointing out its deep underlying flaw: the tension between the " static " nature of AGM revision (which was originally tailored for revision of only purely ontic beliefs, and can be applied to higher-order beliefs only if given a " backwards-looking " interpretation) and the fact that, semantically speaking, any Ramsey conditional must be a modal operator (more precisely, a dynamic-epistemic one). Thus, a belief about a Ramsey conditional is in fact a higher-order belief, hence the AGM revision postulates are not applicable to it, except in their " backwards-looking " interpretation. But that interpretation is consistent only with a restricted (weak) version of Ramsey's test (in-applicable to already revised theories). The solution out of the conundrum is twofold: either accept only the weak Ramsey test; or replace the AGM revision operator * by a truly " dynamic " revision operator ⊗, which will not satisfy the AGM axioms, but will do something better: it will " keep up with reality " , correctly describing revision with higher-order beliefs.
We investigate the long-term behavior of iterated belief revision with higher-level doxastic info... more We investigate the long-term behavior of iterated belief revision with higher-level doxastic information. While the classical literature on iterated belief revision [13, 11] deals only with propositional information, we are interested in learning (by an introspective agent, of some partial information about the) answers to various questions Q 1, Q 2, ..., Q n , ... that may refer to the agent’s own beliefs (or even to her belief-revision plans). Here, “learning” can be taken either in the “hard” sense (of becoming absolutely certain of the answer) or in the “soft” sense (accepting some answers as more plausible than others). If the questions are binary (“is φ true or not?”), the agent “learns” a sequence of true doxastic sentences φ 1, ..., φ n , .... “Investigating the long-term behavior” of this process means that we are interested in whether or not the agent’s beliefs, her “knowledge” and her conditional beliefs stabilize eventually or keep changing forever.
We present a logic of conditional doxastic actions, obtained by incorporating ideas from belief r... more We present a logic of conditional doxastic actions, obtained by incorporating ideas from belief revision theory into the usual dynamic logic of epistemic actions. We do this by extending to actions the setting of epistemic plausibility models, developed in Baltag and Smets (2006) for representing (static) conditional beliefs. We introduce
a natural extension of the notion of update product from Baltag and Moss (2004) to plausibility models.
Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science, 2006
In this paper, we present a semantical approach to multi-agent belief revision and belief update.... more In this paper, we present a semantical approach to multi-agent belief revision and belief update. For this, we introduce relational structures called conditional doxastic models (CDM's, for short). We show this setting to be equivalent to an epistemic version of the classical AGM Belief Revision theory. We present a logic of conditional beliefs that is complete w.r.t. CDM's. Moving then to belief updates (sometimes called “dynamic” belief revision) induced by epistemic actions, we consider two particular cases: public announcements and private announcements to subgroups of agents. We show how the standard semantics for these types of updates can be appropriately modified in order to apply it to CDM's, thus incorporating belief revision into our notion of update. We provide a complete axiomatization of the corresponding dynamic doxastic logics. As an application, we solve a “cheating version” of the Muddy Children Puzzle.
In this paper, we develop a notion of doxastic actions, general enough to cover all examples of c... more In this paper, we develop a notion of doxastic actions, general enough to cover all examples of communication actions and most other belief-changing actions encountered in the literature, but also flexible enough to deal with the issue of (static and dynamic) revision of beliefs. This can be seen as a natural extension of the work in [3, 4] on “epistemic actions”, incorporating ideas from the semantics of belief revision and of conditional belief, along the lines pioneered in [2] and [11], but using the conditional belief approach adopted in [22, 10, 9] and adapted in [25] to the context of dynamic belief revision.
Quantum Logic and Quantum Foundations by Sonja Smets
Preprint IQSA 2023, 2023
We take a fresh look at Wigner's Friend thought-experiment and some of its more recent variants a... more We take a fresh look at Wigner's Friend thought-experiment and some of its more recent variants and extensions, such as the Frauchiger-Renner (FR) Paradox. We discuss various solutions proposed in the literature, focusing on a few questions: what is the correct epistemic interpretation of the multiplicity of state assignments in these scenarios; under which conditions can one include classical observers into the quantum state descriptions, in a way that is still compatible with traditional Quantum Mechanics?; under which conditions can one system be admitted as an additional 'observer' from the perspective of another background observer?; when can the standard axioms of multi-agent Epistemic Logic (that allow "knowledge transfer" between agents) be applied to quantum-physical observers? In the last part of the paper, we propose a new answer to these questions, sketch a particular formal implementation of this answer, and apply it to obtain a principled solution to Wigner Friend-type paradoxes.
We introduce a probabilistic modal (dynamic-epistemic) quantum logic PLQP for reasoning about qua... more We introduce a probabilistic modal (dynamic-epistemic) quantum logic PLQP for reasoning about quantum algorithms. We illustrate its expressivity by using it to encode the correctness of the well-known quantum search algorithm, as well as of a quantum protocol known to solve one of the paradigmatic tasks from classical distributed computing (the leader election problem). We also provide a general method (extending an idea employed in the decidability proof in [12]) for proving the decidability of a range of quantum logics, interpreted on finite-dimensional Hilbert spaces. We give general conditions for the applicability of this method, and in particular we apply it to prove the decidability of PLQP.
We address the old question whether a logical understanding of Quantum Mechanics requires abandon... more We address the old question whether a logical understanding of Quantum Mechanics requires abandoning some of the principles of classical logic. Against Putnam and others 1 , our answer is a clear " no ". Philosophically, our argument is based on combining a formal semantic approach, in the spirit of E. W. Beth's proposal of applying Tarski's semantical methods to the analysis of physical theories, with an empirical-experimental approach to Logic, as advocated by both Beth and Put-nam, but understood by us in the view of the operational-realistic tradition of Jauch and Piron, i.e. as an investigation of " the logic of yes-no experiments " (or " questions "). Technically, we use the recently-developed setting of Quantum Dynamic Logic [4, 6] to make explicit the operational meaning of quantum-mechanical concepts in our formal semantics. Based on our recent results [4], we show that the correct interpretation of quantum-logical connectives is dynamical, rather than purely propositional. We conclude that there is no contradiction between classical logic and (our dynamic reinterpretation of) quantum logic. Moreover, we argue that the Dynamic-Logical perspective leads to a better and deeper understanding of the " non-classicality " of quantum behavior than any perspective based on static Propositional Logic.
Mathematical Structures in Computer Science, 2006
The main contribution of this paper is the introduction of a dynamic logic formalism for reasonin... more The main contribution of this paper is the introduction of a dynamic logic formalism for reasoning about information flow in composite quantum systems. This builds on our previous work on a complete quantum dynamic logic for single systems. We extend that work here to a sound (but not necessarily complete) logic for composite systems, which brings together ideas from the Quantum Logic tradition with concepts from (dynamic) Modal Logic and from Quantum Computation. This logic of Quantum Programs (LQP) is capable of expressing important features of quantum measurements and unitary evolutions of multi-partite states, as well as giving logical characterizations to various forms of entanglement (e.g. the Bell states, the GHZ states etc.). We present a finitary syntax, a relational semantics and a sound proof system for this logic. As applications, we use our system to give formal correctness proofs for the Teleportation protocol and for a standard Quantum Secret Sharing protocol; a while range of other quantum circuits and programs, including other known protocols (e.g. Superdense Coding, Entanglement Swapping, Logic-Gate Teleportation etc.), can be similarly verified using our logic.
We present a logical setting that incorporates a belief-revision mechanism within Dynamic-Epistem... more We present a logical setting that incorporates a belief-revision mechanism within Dynamic-Epistemic logic. As the " static " basis for belief revision, we use epistemic plausibility models, together with a modal language based on two epistemic operators: a " knowledge " modality K (the standard S5, fully introspective, notion), and a " safe belief " modality 2 (" weak " , non-negatively-introspective, notion, capturing a version of Lehrer's " indefeasible knowledge "). To deal with " dynamic " belief revision, we introduce action plausibility models, representing various types of " doxastic events ". Action models " act " on state models via a modified update product operation: the " Action-Priority " Update. This is the natural dynamic generalization of AGM revision, giving priority to the incoming information (i.e., to " actions ") over prior beliefs. We completely axiomatize this logic, and show how our update mechanism can " simulate " , in a uniform manner , many different belief-revision policies.
This chapter gives an overview of current dynamic logics that describe belief update and revision... more This chapter gives an overview of current dynamic logics that describe belief update and revision, both for single agents and in multi-agent settings. We employ a mixture of ideas from AGM belief revision theory and dynamic-epistemic logics of information-driven agency. After describing the basic background, we review logics of various kinds of beliefs based on plausibility models, and then go on to various sorts of belief change engendered by changes in current models through hard and soft information. We present matching complete logics with dynamic-epistemic recursion axioms, and develop a very general perspective on belief change by the use of event models and priority update. The chapter continues with three topics that naturally complement the setting of single steps of belief change: connections with probabilistic approaches to belief change, long-term temporal process structure including links with formal learning theory, and multi-agent scenarios of information flow and belief revision in games and social networks. We end with a discussion of alternative approaches, further directions, and windows to the broader literature, while links with relevant philosophical traditions are discussed throughout.
The pre-eminence of logical dynamics, over a static and purely propo-sitional view of Logic, lies... more The pre-eminence of logical dynamics, over a static and purely propo-sitional view of Logic, lies at the core of a new understanding of both formal epistemology and the logical foundations of quantum mechanics. Both areas appear at first sight to be based on purely static propositional formalisms, but in our view their fundamental operators are essentially dynamic in nature. Quantum logic can be best understood as the logic of physically-constrained informational interactions (in the form of measurements and entanglement) between subsystems of a global physical system. Similarly, (multi-agent) epistemic logic is the logic of socially-constrained informational interactions (in the form of direct observations, learning, various forms of communication and testimony) between " subsystems " of a social system. Dynamic Epistemic Logic (DEL) provides us with a unifying setting in which these informational interactions, coming from seemingly very different areas of research, can be fully compared and analyzed. The DEL formalism comes with a powerful set of tools that allows us to make the underlying dynamic/interactive mechanisms fully transparent.
Table of Contents, Preface written by J. van Benthem and Introduction written by A. Baltag and S.... more Table of Contents, Preface written by J. van Benthem and Introduction written by A. Baltag and S. Smets. BOOK: `Johan van Benthem on Logic and Information Dynamics' , Outstanding Contributions to Logic Series, Volume 4, 55 pages, pp. xv-lxix, Springer, 2014.
We present a complete, decidable logic for reasoning about a notion of completely trustworthy (" ... more We present a complete, decidable logic for reasoning about a notion of completely trustworthy (" conclusive ") evidence and its relations to justifiable (implicit) belief and knowledge, as well as to their explicit justifications. This logic makes use of a number of evidence-related notions such as availability, admissibility, and " goodness " of a piece of evidence, and is based on an innovative modification of the Fitting semantics for Artemov's Justification Logic designed to preempt Gettier-type counterexamples. We combine this with ideas from belief revision and awareness logics to provide an account for explicitly justified (defeasible) knowledge based on conclusive evidence that addresses the problem of (logical) omniscience.
We present a logic for reasoning about the evidence-based knowledge and beliefs and the evidentia... more We present a logic for reasoning about the evidence-based knowledge and beliefs and the evidential dynamics of non-logically-omniscient agents. We do this by adapting key tools and techniques from Dynamic Epistemic Logic, Justification Logic, and Belief Revision so as to provide a lightweight, yet fine-grained approach that characterizes well-known epistemic and doxastic attitudes in terms of the evidential reasoning that justifies these attitudes. We then add the dynamic operations of evidence introduction, evidence-based inference, strong acceptance of new evidence (evidential " upgrade "), and irrevocable acceptance of additional evidence (evidential " update "). We exemplify our theory by providing a formal dynamic account of Lehrer's well-known Gettier-type scenario involving the famous Ferrari and the infamous Messrs. Nogot and Havit.
In this paper we re-evaluate Segerberg's " full DDL " (Dynamic Doxas-tic Logic) from the perspect... more In this paper we re-evaluate Segerberg's " full DDL " (Dynamic Doxas-tic Logic) from the perspective of Dynamic Epistemic Logic (DEL), in its belief-revision-friendly incarnation. We argue that a correct version of full DDL must give up the Success Postulate for dynamic revision. Next, we present (an appropriately generalized and simplified version of) full DDL, showing that it is a generalization of the so-called Topo-logic of Moss and Parikh. We construct AGM-friendly versions of full DDL, corresponding to various revising/contracting operations considered in the Belief Revision literature. We show that DDL can internalize inside one model the " external " doxastic dynamics of DEL, as well as the evidential dynamics investigated by van Benthem and Pacuit. In our Conclusions section, we compare three styles of modeling doxastic dynamics: DDL, DEL and PDL/ETL (the Propo-sitional Dynamic Logic approach, with its Epistemic Temporal Logic variant).
We investigate the issue of reaching doxastic agreement among the agents of a group by " sharing ... more We investigate the issue of reaching doxastic agreement among the agents of a group by " sharing " information via successive acts of sincere, persuasive and public communication within the group. The topic relates to " preference aggregation " in Social Choice theory, where the problem is to find a natural and fair merge operation for aggregating the agents' preferences into a single group preference. In this paper we study this topic within the setting of Dynamic Epistemic Logic (DEL) and its recent extensions to belief revision theory. First we interpret the agents' preference relations as " doxastic preferences " or " doxastic plausibility orders ". Using these plausibility structures, we can express several types of relevant doxastic attitudes: ranging from an agent's simple beliefs and conditional beliefs to her defeasible knowledge and irrevocable knowledge. Next, we model communication via a series of doxastic/epistemic actions that affect the agent's plausibility structures. Because these structures can change in different ways, a group of agents has to adopt a specific communication protocol in order to aggregate their doxastic attitudes. We study the type of merges that are realizable via specific communication protocols and we highlight important factors which may influence the result, such as " the order of the speakers " , or the listeners' doxastic attitudes towards the speakers (i.e their opinions concerning the reliability of the incoming information).
While propositional doxastic attitudes , like knowledge and belief, capture an agent's opinion ab... more While propositional doxastic attitudes , like knowledge and belief, capture an agent's opinion about certain propositions, her attitudes towards sources of information express her opinion about the reliability (or trustwor-thiness) of those sources. If an agent trusts a witness, then she will, within certain limits, tend to accept his testimony as veridical. But if she considers the witness to be a notorious liar, she may come to believe the opposite of what he tells her. In this paper, we put such attitudes towards sources (or dynamic (doxastic) attitudes) center stage, and formalize them as belief-revision strategies: policies governing how an agent changess her beliefs whenever new information from a certain (type of) source is received. We present a semantic, qualitative modelling of this notion and investigate its properties .
We investigate the process of truth-seeking by iterated belief revision with higher-level doxasti... more We investigate the process of truth-seeking by iterated belief revision with higher-level doxastic information. In this paper we elaborate further on the main results and formal settings provided in [8, 7], linking this previous work to the issue of truth approximation. On the one hand our previous results show that on an initial finite Kripke model, a truthful belief upgrade (with the same true sentence) may be repeated 'ad infinitum', without ever reaching a fixed point of the belief-revision process. On the other hand, we proved some positive convergence results: the agent's simple beliefs (and knowledge) will eventually stabilize when iterating updates or truthful radical upgrades. In this paper we apply these results to the problem of convergence to the truth. We study the conditions under which the fixed points of iterated upgrades (if they are reached) would coincide with the truth. We highlight the case in which from some moment onwards, at least if the agent completely or highly trusts the source of new information, she can predict all the future correct answers to a series of questions (but without ever knowing for sure that this is the case). We give two different conditions ensuring that beliefs eventually converge on " full (complete) truth " , as well as conditions ensuring only that they converge to true (but not necessarily complete) beliefs.
What happens in the long term with a group’s beliefs, knowledge and “epistemic states” (fully des... more What happens in the long term with a group’s beliefs, knowledge and “epistemic states” (fully describable in fact by conditional beliefs), when receiving (or exchanging) a sequence of public announcements of truthful but uncertain information? Do the agents’ beliefs (or knowledge, or conditional beliefs, or other doxastic attitudes such as “strong beliefs”) reach a fixed point? Or do they exhibit instead a cyclic behavior, oscillating forever? These questions are of obvious importance for Belief Revision theory, Learning theory and Social Choice theory,
and may have some relevance to Game Theory as well. In fact, some of these questions came to our attention due to a recent talk by J. van Benthem (Chennai, January 2009), in which he was refining his previous “dynamic” analysis [14] of backward induction solution in perfect information games. This extended abstract provides some partial answers to some of the questions above, as well as a convenient setting for investigating further the ones that are still open.
We present a semantic analysis of the Ramsey test, pointing out its deep underlying flaw: the ten... more We present a semantic analysis of the Ramsey test, pointing out its deep underlying flaw: the tension between the " static " nature of AGM revision (which was originally tailored for revision of only purely ontic beliefs, and can be applied to higher-order beliefs only if given a " backwards-looking " interpretation) and the fact that, semantically speaking, any Ramsey conditional must be a modal operator (more precisely, a dynamic-epistemic one). Thus, a belief about a Ramsey conditional is in fact a higher-order belief, hence the AGM revision postulates are not applicable to it, except in their " backwards-looking " interpretation. But that interpretation is consistent only with a restricted (weak) version of Ramsey's test (in-applicable to already revised theories). The solution out of the conundrum is twofold: either accept only the weak Ramsey test; or replace the AGM revision operator * by a truly " dynamic " revision operator ⊗, which will not satisfy the AGM axioms, but will do something better: it will " keep up with reality " , correctly describing revision with higher-order beliefs.
We investigate the long-term behavior of iterated belief revision with higher-level doxastic info... more We investigate the long-term behavior of iterated belief revision with higher-level doxastic information. While the classical literature on iterated belief revision [13, 11] deals only with propositional information, we are interested in learning (by an introspective agent, of some partial information about the) answers to various questions Q 1, Q 2, ..., Q n , ... that may refer to the agent’s own beliefs (or even to her belief-revision plans). Here, “learning” can be taken either in the “hard” sense (of becoming absolutely certain of the answer) or in the “soft” sense (accepting some answers as more plausible than others). If the questions are binary (“is φ true or not?”), the agent “learns” a sequence of true doxastic sentences φ 1, ..., φ n , .... “Investigating the long-term behavior” of this process means that we are interested in whether or not the agent’s beliefs, her “knowledge” and her conditional beliefs stabilize eventually or keep changing forever.
We present a logic of conditional doxastic actions, obtained by incorporating ideas from belief r... more We present a logic of conditional doxastic actions, obtained by incorporating ideas from belief revision theory into the usual dynamic logic of epistemic actions. We do this by extending to actions the setting of epistemic plausibility models, developed in Baltag and Smets (2006) for representing (static) conditional beliefs. We introduce
a natural extension of the notion of update product from Baltag and Moss (2004) to plausibility models.
Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science, 2006
In this paper, we present a semantical approach to multi-agent belief revision and belief update.... more In this paper, we present a semantical approach to multi-agent belief revision and belief update. For this, we introduce relational structures called conditional doxastic models (CDM's, for short). We show this setting to be equivalent to an epistemic version of the classical AGM Belief Revision theory. We present a logic of conditional beliefs that is complete w.r.t. CDM's. Moving then to belief updates (sometimes called “dynamic” belief revision) induced by epistemic actions, we consider two particular cases: public announcements and private announcements to subgroups of agents. We show how the standard semantics for these types of updates can be appropriately modified in order to apply it to CDM's, thus incorporating belief revision into our notion of update. We provide a complete axiomatization of the corresponding dynamic doxastic logics. As an application, we solve a “cheating version” of the Muddy Children Puzzle.
In this paper, we develop a notion of doxastic actions, general enough to cover all examples of c... more In this paper, we develop a notion of doxastic actions, general enough to cover all examples of communication actions and most other belief-changing actions encountered in the literature, but also flexible enough to deal with the issue of (static and dynamic) revision of beliefs. This can be seen as a natural extension of the work in [3, 4] on “epistemic actions”, incorporating ideas from the semantics of belief revision and of conditional belief, along the lines pioneered in [2] and [11], but using the conditional belief approach adopted in [22, 10, 9] and adapted in [25] to the context of dynamic belief revision.
Preprint IQSA 2023, 2023
We take a fresh look at Wigner's Friend thought-experiment and some of its more recent variants a... more We take a fresh look at Wigner's Friend thought-experiment and some of its more recent variants and extensions, such as the Frauchiger-Renner (FR) Paradox. We discuss various solutions proposed in the literature, focusing on a few questions: what is the correct epistemic interpretation of the multiplicity of state assignments in these scenarios; under which conditions can one include classical observers into the quantum state descriptions, in a way that is still compatible with traditional Quantum Mechanics?; under which conditions can one system be admitted as an additional 'observer' from the perspective of another background observer?; when can the standard axioms of multi-agent Epistemic Logic (that allow "knowledge transfer" between agents) be applied to quantum-physical observers? In the last part of the paper, we propose a new answer to these questions, sketch a particular formal implementation of this answer, and apply it to obtain a principled solution to Wigner Friend-type paradoxes.
We introduce a probabilistic modal (dynamic-epistemic) quantum logic PLQP for reasoning about qua... more We introduce a probabilistic modal (dynamic-epistemic) quantum logic PLQP for reasoning about quantum algorithms. We illustrate its expressivity by using it to encode the correctness of the well-known quantum search algorithm, as well as of a quantum protocol known to solve one of the paradigmatic tasks from classical distributed computing (the leader election problem). We also provide a general method (extending an idea employed in the decidability proof in [12]) for proving the decidability of a range of quantum logics, interpreted on finite-dimensional Hilbert spaces. We give general conditions for the applicability of this method, and in particular we apply it to prove the decidability of PLQP.
We address the old question whether a logical understanding of Quantum Mechanics requires abandon... more We address the old question whether a logical understanding of Quantum Mechanics requires abandoning some of the principles of classical logic. Against Putnam and others 1 , our answer is a clear " no ". Philosophically, our argument is based on combining a formal semantic approach, in the spirit of E. W. Beth's proposal of applying Tarski's semantical methods to the analysis of physical theories, with an empirical-experimental approach to Logic, as advocated by both Beth and Put-nam, but understood by us in the view of the operational-realistic tradition of Jauch and Piron, i.e. as an investigation of " the logic of yes-no experiments " (or " questions "). Technically, we use the recently-developed setting of Quantum Dynamic Logic [4, 6] to make explicit the operational meaning of quantum-mechanical concepts in our formal semantics. Based on our recent results [4], we show that the correct interpretation of quantum-logical connectives is dynamical, rather than purely propositional. We conclude that there is no contradiction between classical logic and (our dynamic reinterpretation of) quantum logic. Moreover, we argue that the Dynamic-Logical perspective leads to a better and deeper understanding of the " non-classicality " of quantum behavior than any perspective based on static Propositional Logic.
Mathematical Structures in Computer Science, 2006
The main contribution of this paper is the introduction of a dynamic logic formalism for reasonin... more The main contribution of this paper is the introduction of a dynamic logic formalism for reasoning about information flow in composite quantum systems. This builds on our previous work on a complete quantum dynamic logic for single systems. We extend that work here to a sound (but not necessarily complete) logic for composite systems, which brings together ideas from the Quantum Logic tradition with concepts from (dynamic) Modal Logic and from Quantum Computation. This logic of Quantum Programs (LQP) is capable of expressing important features of quantum measurements and unitary evolutions of multi-partite states, as well as giving logical characterizations to various forms of entanglement (e.g. the Bell states, the GHZ states etc.). We present a finitary syntax, a relational semantics and a sound proof system for this logic. As applications, we use our system to give formal correctness proofs for the Teleportation protocol and for a standard Quantum Secret Sharing protocol; a while range of other quantum circuits and programs, including other known protocols (e.g. Superdense Coding, Entanglement Swapping, Logic-Gate Teleportation etc.), can be similarly verified using our logic.
International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 2005
We present two equivalent axiomatizations for a logic of quantum actions: one in terms of quantum... more We present two equivalent axiomatizations for a logic of quantum actions: one in terms of quantum transition systems, and the other in terms of quantum dynamic algebras. The main contribution of the paper is conceptual, offering a new view of quantum structures in terms of their underlying logical dynamics. We also prove Representation Theorems, showing these axiomatizations to be complete with respect to the natural Hilbert-space semantics. The advantages of this setting are many: (1) it provides a clear and intuitive dynamic-operational meaning to key postulates (e.g. Orthomodularity, Covering Law); (2) it reduces the complexity of the Solèr–Mayet axiomatization by replacing some of their key higher-order concepts (e.g. “automorphisms of the ortholattice”) by first-order objects (“actions”) in our structure; (3) it provides a link between traditional quantum logic and the needs of quantum computation.
We propose an expressive but decidable logic for reasoning about quantum systems. The logic is en... more We propose an expressive but decidable logic for reasoning about quantum systems. The logic is endowed with tensor operators to capture properties of composite systems, and with probabilistic predica-tion formulas P ≥r (s), saying that a quantum system in state s will yield the answer 'yes' (i.e. it will collapse to a state satisfying property P) with a probability at least r whenever a binary measurement of property P is performed. Besides first-order quantifiers ranging over quantum states, we have two second-order quantifiers, one ranging over quantum-testable properties, the other over quantum " actions ". We use this formalism to express the correctness of some quantum programs. We prove decidabil-ity, via translation into the first-order logic of real numbers.
In this paper we introduced a new variant of quantum dynamic logic, and we proved its decidabilit... more In this paper we introduced a new variant of quantum dynamic logic, and we proved its decidability, by showing that it is translatable into the first-order logic of complex numbers (whose decidability follows from a classical result by Tarski [12]).
International Journal of Theoretical Physics, 2010
In this paper we give a logical analysis of both classical and quantum correlations. We propose a... more In this paper we give a logical analysis of both classical and quantum correlations. We propose a new logical system to reason about the information carried by a complex system composed of several parts. Our formalism is based on an extension of epistemic logic with operators for “group knowledge” (the logic GEL), further extended with atomic sentences describing the results of “joint observations” (the logic LCK). As models we introduce correlation models, as a generalization of the standard representation of epistemic models as vector models. We give sound and complete axiomatizations for our logics, and we use this setting to investigate the relationship between the information carried by each of the parts of a complex system and the information carried by the whole system. In particular we distinguish between the “distributed information”, obtainable by simply pooling together all the information that can be separately observed in any of the parts, and “correlated information”, obtainable only by doing joint observations of the parts (and pooling together the results). Our formalism throws a new light on the difference between classical and quantum information and gives rise to an informational-logical characterization of the notion of “quantum entanglement”.
Synthese, 2012
In this paper we show how ideas coming from two areas of research in logic can reinforce each oth... more In this paper we show how ideas coming from two areas of research in logic can reinforce each other. The first such line of inquiry concerns the “dynamic turn” in logic and especially the formalisms inspired by Propositional Dynamic Logic (PDL); while the second line concerns research into the logical foundations of Quantum Physics, and in particular the area known as Operational Quantum Logic, as developed by Jauch and Piron (Helve Phys Acta 42:842–848, 1969), Piron (Foundations of Quantum Physics, 1976). By bringing these areas together we explain the basic ingredients of Dynamic Quantum Logic, a new direction of research in the logical foundations of physics.
In this paper we show how recent concepts from Dynamic Logic, and in particular from Dynamic Epis... more In this paper we show how recent concepts from Dynamic Logic, and in particular from Dynamic Epistemic logic, can be used to model and interpret quantum behavior. Our main thesis is that all the non-classical properties of quantum systems are explainable in terms of the non-classical flow of quantum information. We give a logical analysis of quantum measurements (formalized using modal operators) as triggers for quantum information flow, and we compare them with other logical operators previously used to model various forms of classical information flow: the " test " operator from Dynamic Logic, the " announcement " operator from Dynamic Epistemic Logic and the " revision " operator from Belief Revision theory. The main points stressed in our investigation are the following: (1) The perspective and the techniques of " logical dynamics " are useful for understanding quantum information flow. (2) Quantum mechanics does not require any modification of the classical laws of " static " propositional logic, but only a non-classical dynamics of information. (3) The main such non-classical feature is that, in a quantum world, all information-gathering actions have some ontic side-effects. (4) This ontic impact can affect in its turn the flow of information, leading to non-classical epistemic side-effects (e.g. a type of non-monotonicity) and to states of " objectively imperfect information ". (5) Moreover, the ontic impact is non-local: an information-gathering action on one part of a quantum system can have ontic side-effects on other, faraway parts of the system.
In this paper I give an overview of how the work on quantum dynamic logic for single systems (as ... more In this paper I give an overview of how the work on quantum dynamic logic for single systems (as developed in [2]) builds on the concepts of (dynamic) modal logic and incorporates the methodology of logical dynamics and action based reasoning into its setting. I show in particular how one can start by modeling quantum actions (i.e. measurements and unitary evolutions) in a dynamic logic framework and obtain a setting that improves on the known theorems in traditional quantum logic (stated in the context of orthomodular lattices).
Current research in Logic is no longer confined to the traditional study of logical consequence o... more Current research in Logic is no longer confined to the traditional study of logical consequence or valid inference. As can be witnessed by the range of topics covered in this special issue, the subject matter of logic encompasses several kinds of informational processes ranging from proofs and inferences to dialogues, observations, measurements, communication and computation. What interests us here is its application to quantum physics: how does logic handle informational processes such as observations and measurements of quantum systems? What are the basic logical principles fit to handle and reason about quantum physical processes? These are the central questions in this paper. It is my aim to provide the reader with some food for thought and to give some pointers to the literature that provide an easy access to this field of research. In the next section I give a brief historical sketch of the origin of the quantum logic project. Next I will explain the theory of orthomodular lattices in section 2. Section 3 covers the syntax and semantics of traditional quantum logic. In section 4, I focus on the limits of quantum logic, dealing in particular with the implication problem. This paves the way to section 5 on modal quantum logic. I end with section 6 on dynamic quantum logic, giving the reader a taste of one of the latest new developments in the field.
We give a logical analysis of quantum measurements as forms of information update. We enumerate s... more We give a logical analysis of quantum measurements as forms of information update. We enumerate some of the " lessons " that Logic can learn from Quantum Mechanics: (1) the importance of logical dynamics; (2) the fact that quantum physics does not require any modification of the classical laws of " static " propositional logic, but only a non-classical dynamics of information flow; (3) the fact that all information-gathering actions have ontic side-effects; (4) the fact that this ontic impact might in its turn affect the flow of information, leading to non-classical epistemic effects and to states of " objectively imperfect information " .
Mathematical Structures in Computer Science, 2004
We present a logical calculus for reasoning about information flow in quantum programs. In partic... more We present a logical calculus for reasoning about information flow in quantum programs. In particular we introduce a dynamic logic that is capable of dealing with
quantum measurements, unitary evolutions and entanglements in compound quantum systems. We give a syntax and a relational semantics in which we abstract away from phases and probabilities. We present a sound proof system for this logic, and we show how to characterize by logical means various forms of entanglement (e.g. the Bell states) and various linear operators. As an example we sketch an analysis of the teleportation protocol.
We analyze G.M. Hardegree’s interpretation of the Sasaki hook as a Stalnaker conditional and expl... more We analyze G.M. Hardegree’s interpretation of the Sasaki hook as a Stalnaker conditional and explain how he makes use of the basic conceptual machinery of OQL, i.e. the operational quantum logic which originated with the Geneva Approach to the foundations of physics. In particular we focus on measurements which are ideal and of the first kind, since these encode the content of the so-called Sasaki projections within the Geneva Approach. The Sasaki projections play a fundamental role when analyzing the condition under which the properties expressed by Sasaki hooks can be considered as actual. We finish with a note on how the Sasaki hook can be conceived as “assigning causes for properties to be actual”, which links the interpretation of G.M. Hardegree to what has been called “dynamic OQL”.
In this article we propose an approach that models the truth behavior of cognitive entities (i.e.... more In this article we propose an approach that models the truth behavior of cognitive entities (i.e. sets of connected propositions) by taking into account in a very explicit way the possible influence of the cognitive person (the one that interacts with the considered cognitive entity). Hereby we specifically apply the mathematical formalism of quantum mechanics because of the fact that this formalism allows the description of real contextual influences, i.e. the influence of the measuring apparatus on the physical entity. We concentrated on the typical situation of the liar paradox and have shown that (1) the truth-false state of this liar paradox can be represented by a quantum vector of the non-product type in a finite dimensional complex Hilbert space and the different cognitive interactions by the actions of the corresponding quantum projections, (2) the typical oscillations between false and truth - the paradox -is now quantum dynamically described by a Schrodinger equation. We analyse possible philosophical implications of this result.
In this paper we concentrate on the nature of the liar paradox as a cognitive entity; a consisten... more In this paper we concentrate on the nature of the liar paradox as a cognitive entity; a consistently testable configuration of properties. We elaborate further on a quantum mechanical model [Aerts, Broekaert, Smets 1999] that has been proposed to analyze the dynamics involved, and we focus on the interpretation and concomitant philosophical picture. Some conclusions we draw from our model favor an effective realistic interpretation of cognitive reality.
We study the learning power of iterated belief-revision methods. Successful learning is understoo... more We study the learning power of iterated belief-revision methods. Successful learning is understood as convergence to correct, i.e., true, beliefs. We focus on the issue of universality: whether or not a particular belief-revision method is able to learn everything that in principle is learnable. We provide a general framework for interpreting belief-revision policies as learning methods. We focus on three popular cases: conditioning , lexicographic revision, and minimal revision. Our main result is that conditioning and lexicographic revision can drive a universal learning mechanism, provided that the observations include only and all true data, and provided that a non-standard, i.e., non-well-founded prior plausibility relation is allowed. We show that a standard, i.e., well-founded belief-revision setting is in general too narrow to guarantee universality of any learning method based on belief revision. We also show that minimal revision is not universal. Finally , we consider situations in which observational errors (false observations) may occur. Given a fairness condition, which says that only finitely many errors occur, and that every error is eventually corrected, we show that lexicographic revision is still universal in this setting, while the other two methods are not.
We investigate the issues of inductive problem-solving and learning by doxas-tic agents. We provi... more We investigate the issues of inductive problem-solving and learning by doxas-tic agents. We provide topological characterizations of solvability and learnability, and we use them to prove that AGM-style belief revision is " universal " , i.e., that every solvable problem is solvable by AGM conditioning.
We analyze the learning power of iterated belief revision methods, and in particular their univer... more We analyze the learning power of iterated belief revision methods, and in particular their universality: whether or not they can learn everything that can be learnt. We look in particular at three popular methods: conditioning, lexicographic revision and minimal revision. Our main result is that conditioning and lexicographic revision are universal on arbitrary epistemic states, provided that the observational setting is sound and complete (only true data are observed, and all true data are eventually observed) and provided that a non-standard (non-well-founded) prior plausibility relation is allowed. We show that a standard (well-founded) belief-revision setting is in general too narrow for this. We also show that minimal revision is not universal. Finally, we consider situations in which observational errors (false observations) may occur. Given a fairness condition (saying that only fi nitely many errors occur, and that every error is eventually corrected), we show that lexicographic revision is
still universal in this setting, while the other two methods are not.
We introduce a new topological semantics for evidence, evidence-based justifications, belief and ... more We introduce a new topological semantics for evidence, evidence-based justifications, belief and knowledge. This setting builds on the evidence model framework of van Benthem and Pacuit, as well as our own previous work on (a topological semantics for) Stalnaker's doxastic-epistemic axioms. We prove completeness, decidability and finite model property for the associated logics, and we apply this setting to analyze key issues in Epistemology: " no false lemma " Gettier examples, misleading defeaters, and undefeated justification versus undefeated belief.
Stalnaker introduced a combined epistemic-doxastic logic that can formally express a strong conce... more Stalnaker introduced a combined epistemic-doxastic logic that can formally express a strong concept of belief, a concept which captures the 'epistemic possibility of knowledge'. In this paper we first provide the most general extensional semantics for this concept of 'strong belief', which validates the principles of Stalnaker's epistemic-doxastic logic. We show that this general extensional semantics is a topological semantics, based on so-called extremally disconnected topological spaces. It extends the standard topological interpretation of knowledge (as the interior operator) with a new topological semantics for belief. Formally, our belief modality is interpreted as the 'closure of the interior'. We further prove that in this semantics the logic KD45 is sound and complete with respect to the class of extremally disconnected spaces and we compare our approach to a different topological setting in which belief is interpreted in terms of the derived set operator. In the second part of the paper we study (static) belief revision as well as belief dynamics by providing a topological semantics for conditional belief and belief update modalities, respectively. Our investigation of dynamic belief change, is based on hereditarily extremally disconnected spaces. The logic of belief KD45 is sound and complete with respect to the class of hereditarily extremally disconnected spaces (under our proposed semantics), while the logic of knowledge is required to be S4.3. Finally, we provide a complete axiomatization of the logic of conditional belief and knowledge, as well as a complete axiomatization of the corresponding dynamic logic.
We present a new topological semantics for doxastic logic, in which the belief modality is interp... more We present a new topological semantics for doxastic logic, in which the belief modality is interpreted as the closure of the interior operator. We show that this semantics is the most general (exten-sional) semantics validating Stalnaker's epistemic-doxastic axioms [22] for " strong belief " , understood as subjective certainty. We prove two completeness results, and we also give a topological semantics for update (dynamic conditioning), i.e. the operation of revising with " hard information " (modeled by restricting the topology to a subspace). Using this, we show that our setting fits well with the defeasibility analysis of knowledge [18]: topological knowledge coincides with undefeated true belief. Finally, we compare our semantics to the older topological interpretation of belief in terms of Cantor derivative [23].
We introduce a new topological semantics for belief logics in which the belief modality is interp... more We introduce a new topological semantics for belief logics in which the belief modality is interpreted as the interior of the closure of the interior operator. We show that the system wKD45, a weakened version of KD45, is sound and complete w.r.t. the class of all topological spaces. Moreover, we point out a problem regarding updates on extremally disconnected spaces that appears in the setting of [1] and show that our proposal for topological belief semantics on all topological spaces constitutes a solution for it. While generalizing the topological belief semantics proposed in [1] to all spaces, we model conditional beliefs and updates and give complete axiomatizations of the corresponding logics.
We take a logical approach to threshold models, used to study the diffusion of opinions, new tech... more We take a logical approach to threshold models, used to study the diffusion of opinions, new technologies, infections, or behaviors in social networks. Threshold models consist of a network graph of agents connected by a social relationship and a threshold value which regulates the diffusion process. Agents adopt a new behavior/product/opinion when the proportion of their neighbors who have already adopted it meets the threshold. Under this adoption policy, threshold models develop dynamically towards a guaranteed fixed point. We construct a minimal dynamic propositional logic to describe the threshold dynamics and show that the logic is sound and complete. We then extend this framework with an epistemic dimension and investigate how information about more distant neighbors' behavior allows agents to anticipate changes in behavior of their closer neighbors. Overall, our logical formalism captures the interplay between the epistemic and social dimensions in social networks.
In this paper, we investigate the social herding phenomenon known as informational cascades, in w... more In this paper, we investigate the social herding phenomenon known as informational cascades, in which sequential inter-agent communication might lead to epistemic failures at group level, despite availability of information that should be sufficient to track the truth. We model an example of a cascade, and check the correctness of the individual reasoning of each agent involved, using two alternative logical settings: an existing probabilistic dynamic epistemic logic, and our own novel logic for counting evidence. Based on this analysis, we conclude that cascades are not only likely to occur but are sometimes unavoidable by " rational " means: in some situations, the group's inability to track the truth is the direct consequence of each agent's rational attempt at individual truth-tracking. Moreover, our analysis shows that this is even so when rationality includes unbounded higher-order reasoning powers (about other agents' minds and about the belief-formation-and-aggregation protocol, including an awareness of the very possibility of cascades), as well as when it includes simpler, non-Bayesian forms of heuristic reasoning (such as comparing the amount of evidence pieces).
We investigate the discrete (finite) case of the Popper–Renyi theory of conditional probability, ... more We investigate the discrete (finite) case of the Popper–Renyi theory of conditional probability, introducing discrete conditional probabilistic models for knowledge and conditional belief, and comparing them with the more standard plau-sibility models. We also consider a related notion, that of safe belief, which is a weak (non-negatively introspective) type of " knowledge ". We develop a probabilistic version of this concept (" degree of safety ") and we analyze its role in games. We completely axiomatize the logic of conditional belief, knowledge and safe belief over conditional probabilistic models. We develop a theory of probabilistic dynamic belief revision, introducing probabilistic " action models " and proposing a notion of probabilistic update product, that comes together with appropriate reduction laws.
We investigate the discrete (finite) case of the Popper-Renyi theory of conditional probability, ... more We investigate the discrete (finite) case of the Popper-Renyi theory of conditional probability, introducing discrete conditional probabilis-tic models for knowledge and conditional belief, and comparing them with the more standard plausibility models. We also consider a related notion, that of safe belief, which is a weak (non-negatively introspective) type of " knowledge ". We develop a probabilistic version of this concept (" degree of safety ") and we analyze its role in games. We completely axiomatize the logic of conditional belief, knowledge and safe belief over conditional probabilistic models. We develop a theory of probabilistic dynamic belief revision, introducing " action models " and a notion of probabilistic update product, that comes together with appropriate reduction laws.
We investigate the discrete (finite) case of the Popper-Renyi theory of conditional probability, ... more We investigate the discrete (finite) case of the Popper-Renyi theory of conditional probability, introducing discrete conditional probabilistic models for (multi-agent) knowledge and conditional belief, and comparing them with the more standard plausibility models. We also consider a related notion, that of safe belief, which is a weak (non-negatively introspective) type of “knowledge”, and we analyze its role in games. We completely axiomatize the logic of conditional belief, knowledge and safe belief. We develop a theory of dynamic belief revision over probabilistic models, by introducing “action models” and a notion of update, and showing how various belief-revisions policies considered in the literature, as well as various forms of communication and other belief-changing events, can be represented in this setting. We give a complete and decidable set of axioms for a qualitative dynamic logic of belief-revising actions over probabilistic models.
arXiv (Cornell University), Jul 4, 2023
We take a fresh look at Wigner's Friend thought-experiment and some of its more recent variants a... more We take a fresh look at Wigner's Friend thought-experiment and some of its more recent variants and extensions, such as the Frauchiger-Renner (FR) Paradox. We discuss various solutions proposed in the literature, focusing on a few questions: what is the correct epistemic interpretation of the multiplicity of state assignments in these scenarios; under which conditions can one include classical observers into the quantum state descriptions, in a way that is still compatible with traditional Quantum Mechanics?; under which conditions can one system be admitted as an additional 'observer' from the perspective of another background observer?; when can the standard axioms of multi-agent Epistemic Logic (that allow "knowledge transfer" between agents) be applied to quantum-physical observers? In the last part of the paper, we propose a new answer to these questions, sketch a particular formal implementation of this answer, and apply it to obtain a principled solution to Wigner Friend-type paradoxes.
Foundations of Science
We put forward the hypothesis that there exist three basic attitudes towards inconsistencies with... more We put forward the hypothesis that there exist three basic attitudes towards inconsistencies within world views: (1) The inconsistency is tolerated temporarily and is viewed as an expression of a temporary lack of knowledge due to an incomplete or wrong theory. The resolution of the inconsistency is believed to be inherent to the improvement of the theory. This improvement ultimately resolves the contradiction and therefore we call this attitude the ‘regularising’ attitude; (2) The inconsistency is tolerated and both contradicting elements in the theory are retained. This attitude integrates the inconsistency and leads to a paraconsistent calculus; therefore we will call it the paraconsistent attitude. (3) In the third attitude, both elements of inconsistency are considered to be false and the ‘real situation’ is considered something different that can not be described by the theory constructively. This indicates the incompleteness of the theory, and leads us to a paracomplete calcu...
Logic, Rationality, and Interaction, 2019
The paper focuses on a recent challenge brought forward against the interventionist approach to t... more The paper focuses on a recent challenge brought forward against the interventionist approach to the meaning of counterfactual conditionals. According to this objection, interventionism cannot in general account for the interpretation of right-nested counterfactuals, the problem being its strict interventionism. We will report on the results of an empirical study supporting the objection, and we will extend the well-known logic of actual causality with a new operator expressing an alternative notion of intervention that does not suffer from the problem (and thus can account for some critical examples). The core idea of the alternative approach is a new notion of intervention, which operates on the evaluation of the variables in a causal model, and not on their functional dependencies. Our result provides new insights into the logical analysis of causal reasoning.
Journal of Logic and Computation, 2021
This paper proposes different ways of modally defining properties related to the concept of balan... more This paper proposes different ways of modally defining properties related to the concept of balance in signed social networks where relations can be either positive or negative. The motivation is to be able to formally reason about the social phenomenon of group polarization based on balance theory. The starting point is a recently developed basic modal logic that axiomatizes the class of social networks that are balanced up to a certain degree. This property is not modally definable but can be captured using a deduction rule. In this work, we examine different possibilities for extending this basic language to define frame properties such as balance and related properties such as non-overlapping positive and negative relations and collective connectedness as axioms. Furthermore, we define the property of full balance rather than balanced-up-to-a-degree. We look into the complexity of the model checking problem and show a non-compactness result of the extended language. Along the wa...
Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 2020
In this paper we look at different ways of modally defining properties related to the concept of ... more In this paper we look at different ways of modally defining properties related to the concept of balance in signed social networks where relations can be either positive or negative. The motivation is to be able to formally reason about the social phenomenon of group polarization, for which balance theory forms a network-theoretical underpinning. The starting point is a recently developed basic modal logic that axiomatizes the class of social networks that are balanced up to a certain degree. This property is not modally definable but can be captured using a deduction rule. In this paper we examine different possibilities for extending this basic language, in order to, first, be able to define frame properties such as balance and related properties such as non-overlapping positive and negative relations and collective connectedness as axioms, and, second, be able to define the property of full balance rather than balanced-up-to-a-degree. We consider extensions with both static modalities such as the universal and the difference modality, the intersection modality, and nominals known from hybrid logic, as well as dynamic global bridge modalities known from sabotage logic. Along the way we provide axioms for weak balance. Finally, to explore measures of how far a network is from polarization, we consider and compare variations of distance measures between models in relation to balance.
Logic, Rationality, and Interaction, 2021
Applied Sciences
This paper provides an overview of quantum dynamic logics, showing how they have been designed an... more This paper provides an overview of quantum dynamic logics, showing how they have been designed and illustrating how these logics can be applied to verify the correctness of quantum protocols. Similar to the advantages of using dynamic logics to reason about the flow of classical information, the quantum analogues of these logics are tailored to the task of reasoning about the flow of quantum information. We present our logical systems in a modular way, starting with the qualitative logic of quantum measurements and unitary evolutions in single quantum systems, which can already express non-classical effects, e.g., the state-changing interference induced by quantum tests, their non-commutativity, etc. We then move on to logics for compound quantum systems that can capture the non-local features of quantum information: separability, entanglement, correlated measurements, Bell states, etc. We then briefly summarize the logic of quantum probabilities and sketch some applications to quan...
Jaakko Hintikka on Knowledge and Game-Theoretical Semantics, 2018
In this paper we formalize an approach to knowledge that we call Interrogative Epistemology, in t... more In this paper we formalize an approach to knowledge that we call Interrogative Epistemology, in the spirit of Hintikka's "interrogative model" of knowledge. According to our approach, an agent's knowledge is shaped and limited by her interrogative agenda (as defined by her fundamental questions or "epistemic issues"). The dynamic correlate of this postulate is our Selective Learning principle: the agent's agenda limits her potential for knowledge-acquisition. Only meaningful information, that is relevant to one's issues, can really be learnt. We use this approach to propose a new perspective on group knowledge, understood in terms of the epistemic potential of a group of agents: the knowledge that the group may come to possess in common (and thus act upon in a coordinated manner) after all members share their individual information. We argue that the standard notions of group knowledge studied in the literature, ranging from distributed knowledge to common knowledge, do not give us a good measure of a group's epistemic potential. Common knowledge is too weak and too "static", focusing on what the agents can coordinate upon only based on their actual, current knowledge (without any intra-group communication), thus disregarding testimonial knowledge. In contrast, the concept of distributed knowledge is too strong, being based on the assumption that agents can completely internalize all the testimonial evidence received from others, irrespective of the limitations posed by their own interrogative agendas. We show that a group's true epistemic potential typically lies in between common knowledge and distributed knowledge. We propose a logical formalization of these concepts, which comes together with a complete axiomatization, and we use this setting to explain both the triumphs and the failures of collective knowledge, treating examples that range from "collective scientific knowledge" [14, 35, 43] to the so-called "curse of the committee".
We investigate the process of truth-seeking by iterated belief revision with higher-level doxasti... more We investigate the process of truth-seeking by iterated belief revision with higher-level doxastic information. In this paper we elaborate further on the main results and formal settings provided in [8, 7], linking this previous work to the issue of truth approximation. On the one hand our previous results show that on an initial finite Kripke model, a truthful belief upgrade (with the same true sentence) may be repeated ‘ad infinitum’, without ever reaching a fixed point of the belief-revision process. On the other hand, we proved some positive convergence results: the agent’s simple beliefs (and knowledge) will eventually stabilize when iterating updates or truthful radical upgrades. In this paper we apply these results to the problem of convergence to the truth. We study the conditions under which the fixed points of iterated upgrades (if they are reached) would coincide with the truth. We highlight the case in which from some moment onwards, at least if the agent completely or h...
It is well-known that Propositional Dynamic Logic (PDL), and its important fragment known as the ... more It is well-known that Propositional Dynamic Logic (PDL), and its important fragment known as the Hoare Logic, are among the main logical formalisms used in automated program verification of classical programs (based on formal checking of the correctness of a given classical program). It is thus a natural idea to look for quantum analogues of these logics, that could play a similar role in the automated verification of quantum programs. The search for such a “Quantum Propositional Dynamic Logic” has been one of the main objectives of previous investigations by two of the authors (Baltag and Smets) into the logic of quantum information flow. In a series of papers [1, 3, 2, 4, 5, 6, 7], these authors proposed several logical systems: in [1] they focused on single systems1 and presented two equivalent complete axiomatizations for a Logic of Quantum Actions (LQA, allowing actions such as measurements and unitary evolutions, but no entanglements). The completeness result was obtained with...
We present a semantic analysis of the Ramsey test, pointing out its deep underlying flaw: the ten... more We present a semantic analysis of the Ramsey test, pointing out its deep underlying flaw: the tension between the “static” nature of AGM revision (which was originally tailored for revision of only purely ontic beliefs, and can be applied to higher-order beliefs only if given a “backwards-looking” interpretation) and the fact that, semantically speaking, any Ramsey conditional must be a modal operator (more precisely, a dynamic-epistemic one). Thus, a belief about a Ramsey conditional is in fact a higher-order belief, hence the AGM revision postulates are not applicable to it, except in their “backwards-looking” interpretation. But that interpretation is consistent only with a restricted (weak) version of Ramsey’s test (in-applicable to already revised theories). The solution out of the conundrum is twofold: either accept only the weak Ramsey test; or replace the AGM revision operator ∗ by a truly “dynamic” revision operator ⊗, which will not satisfy the AGM axioms, but will do some...
Journal of Logical and Algebraic Methods in Programming, 2019
Building on previous work [4, 5] that bridged Formal Learning Theory and Dynamic Epistemic Logic ... more Building on previous work [4, 5] that bridged Formal Learning Theory and Dynamic Epistemic Logic in a topological setting, we introduce a Dynamic Logic for Learning Theory (DLLT), extending Subset Space Logics [17, 9] with dynamic observation modalities [o]ϕ, as well as with a learning operator L(#» o), which encodes the learner's conjecture after observing a finite sequence of data #» o. We completely axiomatise DLLT, study its expressivity and use it to characterise various notions of knowledge, belief, and learning.
Studia Logica, 2018
We study the learning power of iterated belief revision methods. Successful learning is understoo... more We study the learning power of iterated belief revision methods. Successful learning is understood as convergence to correct, i.e., true, beliefs. We focus on the issue of universality: whether or not a particular belief revision method is able to learn everything that in principle is learnable. We provide a general framework for interpreting belief revision policies as learning methods. We focus on three popular cases: conditioning, lexicographic revision, and minimal revision. Our main result is that conditioning and lexicographic revision can drive a universal learning mechanism, provided that the observations include only and all true data, and provided that a non-standard, i.e., non-well-founded prior plausibility relation is allowed. We show that a standard, i.e., well-founded belief revision setting is in general too narrow to guarantee universality of any learning method based on belief revision. We also show that minimal revision is not universal. Finally, we consider situations in which observational errors (false observations) may occur. Given a fairness condition, which says that only finitely many errors occur, and that every error is eventually corrected, we show that lexicographic revision is still universal in this setting, while the other two methods are not.
Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 2017
We introduce a new topological semantics for belief logics in which the belief modality is interp... more We introduce a new topological semantics for belief logics in which the belief modality is interpreted as the interior of the closure of the interior operator. We show that the system wKD45, a weakened version of KD45, is sound and complete w.r.t. the class of all topological spaces. Moreover, we point out a problem regarding updates on extremally disconnected spaces that appears in the setting of [1] and show that our proposal for topological belief semantics on all topological spaces constitutes a solution for it. While generalizing the topological belief semantics proposed in [1] to all spaces, we model conditional beliefs and updates and give complete axiomatizations of the corresponding logics.
Readings in Formal Epistemology, 2016
We present a logical setting that incorporates a belief-revision mechanism within Dynamic-Epistem... more We present a logical setting that incorporates a belief-revision mechanism within Dynamic-Epistemic logic. As the "static" basis for belief revision, we use epistemic plausibility models, together with a modal language based on two epistemic operators: a "knowledge" modality K (the standard S5, fully introspective, notion), and a "safe belief" modality 2 ("weak", non-negatively-introspective, notion, capturing a version of Lehrer's "indefeasible knowledge"). To deal with "dynamic" belief revision, we introduce action plausibility models, representing various types of "doxastic events". Action models "act" on state models via a modified update product operation: the "Action-Priority" Update. This is the natural dynamic generalization of AGM revision, giving priority to the incoming information (i.e. to "actions") over prior beliefs. We completely axiomatize this logic, and show how our update mechanism can "simulate", in a uniform manner, many different belief-revision policies.
In this paper, we investigate the social herding phenomenon known as "informational cascades... more In this paper, we investigate the social herding phenomenon known as "informational cascades", in which sequential inter-agent communication might lead to epistemic failures at group level, despite availability of information that should be sufficient to track the truth. We model an example of a cascade, and check the correctness of the individual reasoning of each agent involved, using two alternative logical settings: an existing probabilistic dynamic epistemic logic, and our own novel logic for counting evidence. Based on this analysis, we conclude that cascades are not only likely to occur but are sometimes unavoidable by "rational" means: in some situations, the group's inability to track the truth is the direct consequence of each agent's rational attempt at individual truth-tracking. Moreover, our analysis shows that this is even so when rationality includes unbounded higher-order reasoning powers (about other agents' minds and about the belief...
Proceedings of the 13th Conference on Theoretical Aspects of Rationality and Knowledge, 2011
We analyze the learning power of iterated belief revision methods, and in particular their univer... more We analyze the learning power of iterated belief revision methods, and in particular their universality: whether or not they can learn everything that can be learnt. We look in particular at three popular methods: conditioning, lexicographic revision and minimal revision. Our main result is that conditioning and lexicographic revision are universal on arbitrary epistemic states, provided that the observational setting is sound and complete (only true data are observed, and all true data are eventually observed) and provided that a non-standard (non-well-founded) prior plausibility relation is allowed. We show that a standard (well-founded) beliefrevision setting is in general too narrow for this. We also show that minimal revision is not universal. Finally, we consider situations in which observational errors (false observations) may occur. Given a fairness condition (saying that only finitely many errors occur, and that every error is eventually corrected), we show that lexicographic revision is still universal in this setting, while the other two methods are not.
Synthese, 2010
We address the old question whether a logical understanding of Quantum Mechanics requires abandon... more We address the old question whether a logical understanding of Quantum Mechanics requires abandoning some of the principles of classical logic. Against Putnam and others (Among whom we may count or not E. W. Beth, depending on how we interpret some of his statements), our answer is a clear "no". Philosophically, our argument is based on combining a formal semantic approach, in the spirit of E. W. Beth's proposal of applying Tarski's semantical methods to the analysis of physical theories, with an empirical-experimental approach to Logic, as advocated by both Beth and Putnam, but understood by us in the view of the operationalrealistic tradition of Jauch and Piron, i.e. as an investigation of "the logic of yes-no experiments" (or "questions"). Technically, we use the recently-developed setting of Quantum Dynamic Logic (Baltag and Smets 2005, 2008) to make explicit the operational meaning of quantum-mechanical concepts in our formal semantics. Based on our recent results (Baltag and Smets 2005), we show that the correct interpretation of quantum-logical connectives is dynamical, rather than purely propositional. We conclude that there is no contradiction between classical logic and (our dynamic reinterpretation of) quantum logic. Moreover, we argue that the Dynamic-Logical perspective leads to a better and deeper understanding of the "non-classicality" of quantum behavior than any perspective based on static Propositional Logic.
Lecture Notes in Computer Science, 2013
We present a new topological semantics for doxastic logic, in which the belief modality is interp... more We present a new topological semantics for doxastic logic, in which the belief modality is interpreted as the closure of the interior operator. We show that this semantics validates Stalnaker's epistemicdoxastic axioms [23], and indeed it is the most general (extensional) semantics validating them. We prove, among other things, that in this semantics the doxastic logic KD45 is sound and complete with respect to the class of all extremally disconnected topological spaces. We also give a topological semantics for conditional belief and show its connection to the operation of updating with "hard information" (modeled by restricting the topology to a subspace). We show that our topological notions fit well with the defeasibility analysis of knowledge: topological knowledge coincides with undefeated true belief. We compare our semantics to the older topological interpretation of belief in terms of Cantor derivative (Steinsvold 2006), arguing in favor of our new semantics. S. Smets contribution to this paper has received funding from the ERC under the European Community's 7th Framework Programme/ERC Grant agreement no. 283963.