The administration of justice in ancient Athens and in Plato's Laws ‐Some comparisons, Politics, 12:1, 116-120 (original) (raw)

Plato and the Reform of Athenian Law: Forthcoming in the

The chapter explores Plato's views about Athenian laws, and his proposal for their reform, advanced in The Laws, in the form of new legislation for the city of Magnesia. After introducing the date and structure of the dialogue, as well as its aims and place in the context of Plato's thought and production, the chapter examines, with a constant comparison with Athens, the constitutional arrangement of the new city, its officials, the judicial system, and the substantive laws on matters of persons and property, citizenship, family law, women, slaves and freedmen, theft, as well as homicide, assault, and wounding. The chapter highlights how Plato's legislative project constitutes a reasoned criticism of contemporary Athenian law.

Plato and Athenian Justice

History of Political Thought, 2015

Plato’s interest in the concept of justice is pronounced and familiar. So too is his antagonism towards classical Athenian democracy. This paper connects the two by locating Plato’s transcendental conceptualization of justice as a direct response to the inter-subjective construction of justice in Athens’ democratic courts. The paper comprises four sections. The first identifies Athens’ popular courts as Plato’s primary institutional target when criticizing democracy. The second examines the difference between the concepts “to dikaion” and “dikaiosynē” and considers the special importance of this distinction in Plato’s Republic. The third examines how “to dikaion” was decided in the popular courts in Athens, and the fourth casts Plato’s treatment of this concept as an intervention against the conceptualization of what is right suggested by these practices. I draw special attention to an affinity between Plato’s approach and the alternative Athenian conception of right advanced in its homicide courts, in which context the gods were thought to be especially interested. I suggest that Plato’s distinctive contribution to the theorization of justice can be understood as an attempt to extend the conception of “to dikaion” advanced in Athens’ homicide courts to cover the field of right in general--with significant consequences for the history of political thought.

Understanding the Role of the Laws in Plato's Statesman

Prolegomena, 2010

In the Statesman, Plato seems to be advocating that in the absence of a true king who will rule independently of laws, the next best thing as far as just rule is concerned is to adhere rigidly to existing laws, whatever they are. The rule of the true king is given as an example of virtuous rule in the sense that virtue politics or jurisprudence holds that laws cannot always deal justly with particular cases. But Plato's view of what we must do when there are no true kings forthcoming seems to preclude a virtue theoretical understanding of politics and laws. In this paper I will investigate the view that the image of the true king, who relies on written laws for convenience only, provides a model for a more realistic appeal to virtue in jurisprudence, that is, a respect of laws that is compatible with equity, in the sense understood by Aristotle.

Civic Piety: Plato and Reverence for the Rule of Law

History of Political Thought, 2017

The Platonic dialogues provide a pronounced critique of the Athenian assembly, where public deliberation and contestation conditioned decision-making, and mass opinion acted as a basis for sound judgment. On Plato’s assessment, the very problem of political judgment thus arises from the coercion made possible by sustaining the conditions of political freedom. This article suggests, however, that whereas the assembly was the locus of Plato’s democratic anxieties, he identified in the popular law-courts an alternative, non-deliberative, and non-contestatory means of forming citizen judgment, through the inculcation of a civic piety predicated on a kind of agnostic reverence for the rule of law.

Law and Political Expertise in Plato's Statesman

Revista Archai, 2024

Remarks made by the Eleatic Visitor at Statesman 293a-300e are often read as implying that laws are hopelessly defective in comparison with expert political knowledge. Specifically, laws seem inadequate to the task of capturing the variability, mutability, and finely-grained detail of human life (294a6-b7). On the other hand, the Visitor endorses a strict form of law-abidingness for non-ideal constitutions. The tension between these positions has greatly exercised scholars. In this paper, I argue for a reading on which (1) the political expert, no less than laws, must rely on "rougher methods," i.e. generalizations across individual cases; (2) lawmaking is a constitutive part of the statesman's expertise; (3) laws are necessary for political communities and their value exceeds the merely instrumental or heuristic.

Building Legal Order in Ancient Athens

Journal of Legal Analysis, 2015

And what is the power of the laws? Is it that, if any of you is attacked and gives a shout, they'll come running to your aid? No, they are just inscribed letters and have no ability to do that. What then is their motive power? You [the jury] are, if you secure them and make them authoritative whenever anyone asks for aid. So the laws are powerful through you and you through the laws. You must therefore stand up for them in just the same way as any individual would stand up for himself if attacked; you must take the view that offenses against the law are common concerns. .. (Demosthenes, Against Meidias, 223-225).

Plato’s Equity Jurisprudence

Plato's Equity Jurisprudence, 2024

Plato is an unfamiliar starting place from which to investigate classical methods of statutory or constitutional interpretation. Yet, as classical texts come, Plato's Laws offers a robust account of legislative intent and the role of statutory interpretation in a properly constituted polis. Moreover, it appears that Plato's account informs Aristotle's famous commentary on epieikeia in Rhetoric and Nicomachean Ethics. First, I examine exactly how Plato grounds proper interpretation in systems with written constitutions, such as Magnesia. This means my descriptive account is mostly relegated to Laws. And this is for good reason. Laws represents an intentional and practical departure from the aspirational components of the Republic. For Plato, equitable interpretation, which is used in particular cases, is a subset of a broader equitable enterprise called Sumplaēroun. Under this doctrine, judicial and legislative practices fill in gaps left by a written constitutional substructure. Second, I compare Plato's and Aristotle's accounts of equitable interpretation. Aristotle clearly borrowed from Plato's insights but departs in important respects. The ambiguity in Aristotle's account, furthermore, can be clarified by viewing it in light of Plato's. Lastly, I lay out further implications of Plato's theory on contemporary Constitutional theory.

Plato’s Socrates and the law code of Athens

Filosofický časopis / The Philosophical Journal, 2021

The paper claims that Socrates’ disawoval of wisdom in the Apology is not to be taken too seriously since it belongs to the rhetorical strategy of the sovereign philosopher who speaks in front of the crowd. In the political arena, the philosopher admits his obligation to become a philosopher-king, but only under a condition: only if his fellow-citizens would freely recognize his legitimacy to rule. As a potential ruler, he has to take into consideration the existing law code which is to be respected if his intended political reform should take place and succeed. The paper stresses that despite Plato’s condemnation of the democratic way of life current in Athens, he never criticizes Athenian laws; Solonian legal reform forms a starting point for his own political project. As a brief glance at the proposed law code of Magnesia in Plato’s Laws makes clear, the Platonic philosopher is full of respect to the Athenian legislative tradition.