Ricoeur's Transcendental Concern: A Hermeneutics of Discourse (original) (raw)
Abstract
This paper argues that Paul Ricoeur’s hermeneutical philosophy attempts to reopen the question of human transcendence in contemporary terms. While his conception of language as self-transcending is deeply Husserlian, Ricoeur also responds to the analytical challenge when he deploys a basic distinction in Fregean logic in order to clarify Heidegger’s phenomenology of world. Riceour’s commitment to a transcendental view is evident in his conception of narrative, which enables him to emphasize the role of the performative in literary reading. The meaning of the self in time provides Ricoeur with a discursive basis for distinguishing his own position from that of Kant and other philosophers in the transcendental tradition.
Loading Preview
Sorry, preview is currently unavailable. You can download the paper by clicking the button above.
References (45)
- See Sluga, H. 1980. Gottlob Frege, 159. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. This reading is particu- larly important when applied to Ricoeur's adaptation of Frege to the task of clarifying Heidegger's notion of world. If Frege was never primarily interested in the question of the object's external existence, then the interpretation of world as reference does not have to be devoid of transcendental import.
- Ricoeur, P. 1977b. The rule of metaphor, 74. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- Ibid., pp. 199-200.
- Cf. Heidegger, Martin. 1996. Being and time, 83-91. Albany: State University of New York Press. In contrasting his own concept of world to that of Descartes, Heidegger develops the basis for a phenomeno- logical hermeneutics that takes Dasein as the starting-point for an original inquiry into the meaning of being. Ricoeur's adaptation of the world-concept would be hermeneutical as well, but it would emphasize how the question of being allows the self to inhabit the world ontologically. Moreover, in the long run, Ricoeurian ontology is less concerned with the difference between being and beings, or with the way that being has been sent to us historically, than with the question of how human identity negotiates the interface between being and time.
- Ricoeur, Paul. 1976. Interpretation theory, 36. Fort Worth: Texas Christian University Press.
- Ibid., pp. 288-90.
- Ricoeur, Paul. 1991. From texts to action II, 107. London: Athlone Press.
- Ibid., pp. 120-21.
- Ricoeur, P. 1985. Time and narrative, vol. 3, 26. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 20 Ibid., p. 27.
- Ibid., p. 31. 22 Ibid., p. 32.
- Ricoeur's reading of Heidegger's masterwork compares in some ways to that of Derrida, Jacques. 1982. Ousia and Grammē: Note on a Note from Being and Time. In Margins of philosophy, 29-67. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Both philosophers contend that Heidegger's attempt to isolate a "vulgar" conception of time from a more "authentic" conception is problematic both methodologi- cally and on the level of hermeneutical consistency. Derrida, however, argues that Heidegger reinstates presence after attempting to reduce Aristotle's time to the metaphysics of a punctual present, whereas Ricoeur contends that Heidegger's acceptance of conflicting conceptions of time is what prevents him from grasping the mediatory potential of narrative.
- Ricoeur, Time and Narrative 3, p. 91. 27 Ibid., p. 125.
- Ibid., p. 168. 30 Ibid., p. 179.
- Gadamer argues that historical consciousness, thoughtfully considered, is never a simple reflection occurring within the closed horizon of the present but that it is always already a listening that accepts the past on its own terms. Listening is the basis for tradition, properly conceived, which allows the past to be interpreted as a "text" that cannot be assimilated to the present any more than it can serve as a substitute for the past. The hermeneutical "fusion of horizons" is thus an accomplishment of historical consciousness that should not be confused with either Hegelian modes of dialectical assimilation or late nineteenth-century positivism. For details, see Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 1991. Truth and method, 304-307. New York: Crossroad.
- Ricoeur, Time and Narrative 3, p. 221. 34 Ibid., p. 221. 35 Ibid., p. 246.
- Kant, Immanuel. 1965. Critique of pure reason, 409. New York: St. Martin's Press. 37 Ibid., p. 414.
- Ricoeur, P. 1994. Oneself as another, 105. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, p. 467.
- Riceour, Oneself as Another, p. 109. 41 Ibid., p. 111. 42 Ibid., p. 112. 43 Ibid., p. 142. 44 Ibid., p. 147.
- Ibid., pp. 180-194.
- Ibid., pp. 191-92.
- R E F E R E N C E S A N D R E A D I N G Abel, O. 2008. Paul Ricoeur's Hermeneutics: From critique to poetics. In Reading ricoeur, ed. sD.M. Kaplan, 183-196. Albany: State University of New York Press.
- Aristotle. 1949. Nichomachean Ethics (trans: Chase, D.P.). London: J. M, Dent and Sons.
- Derrida, J. 1982. Ousia and Grammē: Note on a note from Being and Time. In Margins of philosophy (trans: Bass, A.) 31-67. University of Chicago Press.
- Frege, G. 1952. On sense and reference. In Translations from the philosophical writings of Gottlob Frege (ed. and trans: Geach, P.T. and Black, M.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Gadamer, H.-G. 1977. Philosophical Hermeneutics (trans: Linge, D.E.). Berkeley: University of California Press.
- Gadamer, H.-G. 1991. Truth and method (trans: Weinsheimer, J. and Marshall, D.G.). New York: Crossroad.
- Heidegger, M. 1982. The basic problems of phenomenology (trans: Hofstadter, A.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
- Heidegger, M. 1996. Being and Time (trans: Stambaugh, J.). Albany: State University of New York Press.
- Husserl, E. 1964. The phenomenology of internal time-consciousness (trans: Churchill, J.S.). Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
- Husserl, E. 1999. Cartesian meditations: An introduction to phenomenology (trans: Cairns, D.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publisher.
- Ingarden, R. 1973. The literary work of art: An investigation on the borderlines of ontology, logic and the theory of literature (trans: Grabowicz, G.G.). Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
- Iser, W. 1978. The act of reading: A theory of aesthetic response. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
- Kant, I. 1965. Critique of pure reason (trans: Smith, N.K.). New York: St. Martin's Press.
- Levinas, Emmanuel. 1971. Totality and infinity (trans: Lingis, A.). Pittsburgh: Duquesne University.
- Mohanty, J. N. 1982. Husserl and Frege. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
- Ricoeur, P. 1976. Interpretation theory: Discourse and the surplus of meaning. Forth Worth: Texas Christian University Press.
- Ricoeur, P. 1977a. Feud and philosophy: An essay on interpretation (trans: Savage, D.). New Haven and London: Yale University Press.
- Ricoeur, P. 1977b. The rule of metaphor: Multidisciplinary studies of the creation of meaning in language (trans: Czerny, R.). London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- Ricoeur, P. 1988. Time and narrative, volume 3 (trans: Blamey, K. and Pellauer, D.). Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.
- Ricoeur, P. 1989. The conflict of interpretations: Essays in hermeneutics. In ed. D. Ihde,. London: Athlone Press.
- Ricoeur, P. 1991. From text to action: Essays in hermeneutics II (trans: Blamey, K. and Thompson, J.). London: Athlone Press.
- Ricoeur, P. 1992. Oneself as another (trans: Blamey, K.). Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press.
- Sluga, H. 1980. Gottlob Frege. London and Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
- Wright, G.V. 1971. Explanation and understanding. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Zahavi, D. 2003. Husserl's phenomenology. Stanford: Stanford University Press.