Nonconvergent Electoral Equilibria Under Scoring Rules: Beyond Plurality (original) (raw)

Electoral Competition under Best-Worst Voting Rules

SSRN Electronic Journal, 2016

We characterise multi-candidate pure-strategy equilibria in the Hotelling-Downs spatial election model for the class of best-worst voting rules, in which each voter is endowed with both a positive and a negative vote, i.e., each voter can vote in favour of one candidate and against another one. The weights attached to positive and negative votes in calculating a candidate's net score may be different, so that a negative vote and a positive vote need not cancel out exactly. These rules combine the first-place seeking incentives of plurality with the incentives to avoid being ranked last of antiplurality. We show that these rules generally admit equilibria, which are nonconvergent if and only if the importance of a positive vote exceeds that of a negative vote. The set of equilibria in the latter case is very similar to that of plurality, except that the platforms are less extreme due to the moderating effect of negative votes. Moreover, any degree of dispersion between plurality, at one extreme, and full convergence, at the other, can be attained for the correct choice of the weights.

A survey of equilibrium analysis in spatial models of elections

2005

Elections, as the institution through which citizens choose their political agents, are at the core of representative democracy. It is therefore appropriate that they occupy a central position in the study of democratic politics. The formal analysis of elections traces back to the work of , who apply mathematical methods to understand the equilibrium outcomes of elections. This work, and the literature stemming from it, has focused mainly on the positional aspects of electoral campaigns, where we conceptualize candidates as adopting positions in a "space" of possible policies prior to an election. We maintain this focus by considering the main results for the canonical model of elections, in which candidates simultaneously adopt policy platforms and the winner is committed to the platform on which he or she ran. These models abstract from much of the structural detail of elections, including party primary elections, campaign finance and advertising, the role of interest groups, etc. Nevertheless, in order to achieve a deep understanding of elections in their full complexity, it seems that we must address the equilibrium effects of position-taking by candidates in elections.

Voting Equilibria in Multi-candidate Elections

Journal of Public Economic Theory, 2009

We consider a general plurality voting game with multiple candidates, where voter preferences over candidates are exogenously given. In particular, we allow for arbitrary voter indifferences, as may arise in voting subgames of citizencandidate or locational models of elections. We prove that the voting game admits pure strategy equilibria in undominated strategies. The proof is constructive: we exhibit an algorithm, the "best winning deviation" algorithm, that produces such an equilibrium in finite time. A byproduct of the algorithm is a simple story for how voters might learn to coordinate on such an equilibrium.

The scoring rules in an endogenous election

Plurality rule is mostly criticized from being capable of choosing an alternative considered as worst by a strict majority. This paper considers elections in which the agenda consists of potential candidates strategically choosing whether or not to enter the election. In this context, we examine the ability of scoring rules to fulfil the Condorcet criterion. We show for the case of three potential candidates that Plurality rule is the only scoring rule that satisfies a version of the Condorcet criterion in two cases: 1) when preferences are single-peaked and, 2) when preferences are single-dipped.

Monotonicity paradoxes in three-candidate elections using scoring elimination rules

Social Choice and Welfare, 2017

Scoring Elimination Rules (SER), that give points to candidates according to their rank in voters' preference orders and eliminate the candidate(s) with the lowest number of points, constitute an important class of voting rules. This class of rules, that includes some famous voting methods such as Plurality Runoff or Coombs Rule, suffers from a severe pathology known as monotonicity paradox or monotonicity failure, that is, getting more points from voters can make a candidate a loser and getting fewer points can make a candidate a winner. In this paper, we study three-candidate elections and we identify, under various conditions, which SER minimizes the probability that a monotonicity paradox occurs. We also analyze some strategic aspects of these monotonicity failures. The probability model on which our results are based is the Impartial Anonymous Culture condition, often used in this kind of study. 1 See also Miller (2012) for a (more or less) real-world example. second round is organized which confronts the two candidates with the highest number of votes in the first round and the one who obtains the majority of votes wins. Suppose there are 127 voters whose rankings of the three candidates, a, b and c, are as follows:

Electoral competition with an arbitrary number of participants

2011

In this Thesis, we extend "Hotelling's Electoral Competition Game" to fit a political framework. We assume a sequential choice of postition by the players, who represent candidates in an election, an exit choice, and an incumbent effect – that is, only one player can adopt a specific policy on the policy spectrum. We then find that the subgame-perfect Nash-equilibrium in this game seems to be consistent with many findings in politics nowadays and in the past, for example Duverger's Law or results for the behavior of candidates in the US primary elections. A conjecture exists about the subgame-perfect Nash-equilibrium in this game for N players, and two Theorems concerning this conjecture were formulated and proven in this Thesis.

Possible winners when new candidates are added: the case of scoring rules

Proceedings of The Twenty- …, 2010

Introduction In many real-life collective decision making situations, the set of candidates (or alternatives) may vary while the voting process goes on, and may change at any time before the de-cision is final: some new candidates may join, whereas some others may ...

Electoral competition with policy-motivated candidates

Games and Economic Behavior, 2005

In the multi-dimensional spatial model of elections with two policy-motivated candidates, we prove that the candidates must adopt the same policy platform in equilibrium. Moreover, when the number of voters is odd, if the gradients of the candidates' utility functions point in different directions, then they must locate at some voter's ideal point and a strong symmetry condition must be satisfied: in particular, it must be possible to pair some voters so that their gradients point in exactly opposite directions. If the number of dimensions is more than two, then our condition is knife-edge. When the number of voters is even, the situation is worse: such equilibria never exist, regardless of the dimensionality of the policy space.  2005 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. JEL classification: D72; C72

Three-Candidate Spatial Competition When Candidates Have Valence: Asymmetric Voter Density and Plurality Maximization

2010

We study the effects of stochastic (probabilistic) voting on equilibrium locations, equilibrium vote shares and comparative statics in a setup with three heterogenous candidates and a single-dimensional issue space. Comparing the equilibria with and without stochastic voting, we find that under an appropriate level of uncertainty about voter behavior, the model has a pure strategy Nash Equilibrium (PSNE) that is free from several non-plausible features of the PSNE under deterministic voting. The results are robust to extensions to asymmetric density and plurality maximization.