Introduction: Systematicity, the Nature of Science? (original) (raw)
Related papers
Metascience, 2013
Hoyningen-Huene is rightly famous for his book on Thomas Kuhn's philosophy, Reconstructing Scientific Revolutions: Thomas S. Kuhn's Philosophy of Science. Indeed, to many North American philosophers of science, Hoyningen-Huene is known exclusively as a Kuhn scholar, explicating Kuhn's views and writing on Kuhnian themes, like incommensurability. Hoyningen-Huene's new book, Systematicity, is a departure from Kuhn scholarship, constituting a contribution to general philosophy of science. But this is not an altogether new project. In fact, Hoyningen-Huene reports that he has been working on this project off and on for decades. Systematicity deals with the issue of understanding what distinguishes scientific knowledge from everyday knowledge. This may sound like some version of the demarcation problem, a popular topic in philosophy of science from the 1930s to the 1970s, but the issue that concerns Hoyningen-Huene is different. The demarcation problem was concerned, principally, with distinguishing science from pseudoscience, the alleged bodies of belief that purport to be scientific but in fact are not. Karl Popper regarded the demarcation problem as a pressing issue when he wrote Logic of Scientific Discovery in the 1930s, regarding it as comparable in significance to the problem of induction. Just as the Vienna Circle logical positivists sought to undermine metaphysics with their verification principle, Popper sought to undermine Freudian and Adlerian psychology, and Marxist history by appeal to his demarcation criteria. But instead of accusing the proponents of these theories of indulging in metaphysical flights of fancy, and aspiring to have knowledge about things that exceed our capacity to know, Popper accused them of developing theories that were unfalsifiable, and thus unscientific. Pseudoscientific theories could be reconciled with any possible facts, and thus explained nothing.
in: World Conference on Science. Science for the Twenty-First Century: A New Commitment (ed. by A.M. Cetto), Paris: UNESCO, 2000, pp. 52-56, 2000
Systematicity and the Continuity Thesis
Synthese, 2016
Hoyningen-Huene (Systematicity: the nature of science, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2013) develops an account of what science is, distinguishing it from common sense. According to Hoyningen-Huene, the key distinguishing feature is that science is more systematic. He identifies nine ways in which science is more systematic than common sense. I compare Hoyningen-Huene's view to a view I refer to as the "Continuity Thesis." The Continuity Thesis states that scientific knowledge is just an extension of common sense. This thesis is associated with Quine, Planck, and others. I argue that Hoyningen-Huene ultimately rejects the Continuity Thesis, and I present further evidence to show that the Continuity Thesis is false. I also argue that it is the systematicity of science that ultimately grounds the epistemic authority of science. Hoyningen-Huene thus draws attention to an important feature of science that explains the place of science in contemporary society. Keywords Systematicity • Continuity Thesis • Common sense • Scientific knowledge • Epistemic authority In Systematicity: The Nature of Science Paul Hoyningen-Huene aims to reinvigorate a central question in general philosophy of science: what is the nature of science? A crucial part of his argumentative strategy is to compare scientific inquiry and scientific knowledge to the layperson's approach to inquiry and everyday knowledge. My aim is to draw out some implications of Hoyningen-Huene's view, and in the process clarify his position on the nature of science. I want to contrast his view with
A Reappraisal of the Conceptual Scheme of Science
Philosophy of Science, 1957
1. Argument. Questions that have arisen about the "existence" of elementary particles and other entities of physics have often been dismissed as unprofitable, with the tacit assumption that the categories suitable for the discussion of everyday knowledge are not suitable for the ...
The Need for a Revolution in the Philosophy of Science
There is a need to bring about a revolution in the philosophy of science, interpreted to be both the academic discipline, and the official view of the aims and methods of science upheld by the scientific community. At present both are dominated by the view that in science theories are chosen on the basis of empirical considerations alone, nothing being permanently accepted as a part of scientific knowledge independently of evidence. Biasing choice of theory in the direction of simplicity, unity or explanatory power does not permanently commit science to the thesis that nature is simple or unified. This current "paradigm" is, I argue, untenable. We need a new paradigm, which acknowledges that science makes a hierarchy of metaphysical assumptions concerning the comprehensibility and knowability of the universe, theories being chosen partly on the basis of compatibility with these assumptions. Eleven arguments are given for favouring this new "paradigm" over the current one.