Rules of Belief and the Normativity of Intentional Content (original) (raw)

The Prescriptive Normativity of Mental Content

This paper offers an argument for content normativism, the view that the mind's intentional contents are essentially, prescriptively normative entities. The argument shows that the most prominent objection to the view is unsound. To make this argument, the paper advances a new conception of prescriptive normativity. If this conception is correct, there are three notable consequences. First, the aforementioned objection fails: it rests on a (pervasive) misunderstanding of the requirements for being prescriptively normative (section 2). Second, facts of the form 'subject S possesses concept C' imply that S ought to accord with some conceptual rules, described in the paper, that genuinely prescribe acts that involve C (section 3). Third, it becomes much easier to show, as the last section of the paper does (section 4), that S's obligation to accord with these rules is an essential part of what it is to possess C, and does not follow from other sources of obligation.

Dose the Conceptual Interdependency of Belief and Desire Undermine the Normativity of Content

2015

The normativity of mental content thesis appears to have been influential in contemporary philosophy of mind. Paul Boghossian (2003, 2005) has developed an argument for the normativity of mental content on the basis of two premises, i.e. firstly, the normativity of the notion of belief and secondly, the priority of the notion of belief to the notion of desire. In his recent article Alexander Miller (2008) has criticised Boghossian’s argument for the normativity of mental content. To make the objection against the normativity of content, Miller has argued that the second premise of Boghossian’s argument is mistaken since belief and desire are conceptually interdependent. My purpose in this paper is to show that content normativity thesis prevails Miller's attack. In order to establish the claim I will argue that content is normative even if belief and desire are conceptually interdependent.

Content normativity and the interdependency of belief and desire

UJAH: Unizik Journal of Arts and Humanities, 2015

The normativity of mental content thesis has been very influential in contemporary philosophy of mind and action. Paul Boghossian (2003, 2005) has developed an argument for the normativity of mental content on the basis of two premises-the normativity of the notion of belief and the priority of the notion of belief to the notion of desire. In his article Alexander Miller (2008) has criticised Boghossian's argument for the normativity of mental content. He has argued that the second premise of Boghossian's argument is false to the effect that belief and desire are conceptually interdependent. In this paper, along with proposing a new argument for the normativity of content thesis, I will clarify that the thesis survives Miller's attack.

The normativity of the mental

Philosophical Explorations, 2005

I describe and defend the view in a philosophy of mind that I call ‘Normative Essentialism’, according to which propositional attitudes have normative essences. Those normative essences are ‘horizontal’ rational requirements, by which I mean the requirement to have certain propositional attitudes given other propositional attitudes. Different propositional attitudes impose different horizontal rational requirements. I distinguish a stronger and a weaker version of this doctrine and argue for the weaker version. I explore the consequences for knowledge of mind, and I then consider objections to the view from mental causation, from empirical psychology, and from animals and small children.

Some Remarks on Beliefs and Normativity

2023

Some Remarks on Beliefs and Normativity The aim of this work is to present some recent observations in Cognitive Science about beliefs and the way they are able to originate chains of actions and condition behaviors. It is not my aim to evaluate reliabilist views on beliefs in Philosophical Epistemology, but only to point out that certain scientific observations about the process of belief formation can help us to build an interesting theory. Contemporaneity brings many important challenges to traditional philosophical questions that can potentially broaden our knowledge, hence the importance of considering them in some detail. Some peculiarities of scientific investigation will be presented, some classifications to better understand the phenomenon of study, some difficulties that are imposed on scientific investigation and, finally, some considerations about the normative role of beliefs will be presented.

Normativity and Thought

1999

This paper attempts to describe why it is not possible to account for normative phenomena in non-normative terms. It argues that Papineau’s attempt to locate norms of judgement ‘outside’ content, grounded in an individual’s desires or reasons, mislocates the normativity that is thought to resist appropriation within a ‘world that conceives nature as the realm of law’. It agrees, however, that a theory of content that locates norms ‘inside’ content will not be forthcoming—at least if this is to require fashioning the norms that in some sense govern judgment or thought into individually necessary conditions for contentful states.

The Normativity of Belief and Self-Fulfilling Normative Beliefs

Argues that the proposition ‘There is at least one true normative proposition,’ like the proposition ‘Someone is thinking,’ is true anytime anyone believes it, and, in an important sense, it is made true by someone’s believing it. Although this claim may appear to express the anti-realist position that normative facts are constructed out of our attitudes or judgments, I argue that the key premise from which it is derived is inconsistent with a fully general constructivist position about normative facts. The paper concludes by rehearsing the argument for this premise (originally presented in ‘How Truth Governs Belief’) and defending the argument against two types of objections that recently have been leveled against it.

How Norms (Might) Guide Belief

International Journal of Philosophical Studies

Belief normativism is roughly the view that judgments about beliefs are normative judgments. Kathrin Glüer and Åsa Wikforss (G&W) suggest that there are two ways one could defend this view: by appeal to what might be called 'truth-norms', or by appeal to what might be called 'norms of rationality' or 'epistemic norms'. According to G&W, whichever way the normativist takes, she ends up being unable to account for the idea that the norms in question would guide belief formation. Plausibly, if belief normativism were true, the relevant norms would have to offer such guidance. I argue that G&W’s case against belief normativism is not successful. In section 1, I defend the idea that truth-norms can guide belief formation indirectly via epistemic norms. In section 2, I outline an account of how the epistemic norms might guide belief. Interestingly, this account may involve a commitment to a certain kind of expressivist view concerning judgments about epistemic norms.

In Defense of Constitutivism About Epistemic Normativity

Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 2022

Epistemic Constitutivism (EC) holds that the nature of believing is such that it gives rise to a standard of correctness, and that other epistemic normative notions (e.g., reasons for belief) can be explained in terms of this standard. If defensible, this view promises an attractive and unifying account of epistemic normativity. However, EC faces a forceful objection: that constitutive standards of correctness are never enough for generating normative reasons. This paper aims to defend EC in the face of this objection. I do so in two steps. First, I dispute a crucial assumption underlying the case against EC: that constitutive standards of correctness in general are "reason-giving" only if and because there is also a prior reason to comply with them. Second, I outline a strategy of how EC can meet the challenge of explaining what's special about the activity of believing such that, unlike other standard-governed activities, it is capable of generating normative reasons.